The Yazidi, recent targets of genocide
in its most atrocious form, have sometimes been accused of devil
worship by fundamentalist Christians and Muslims. Of course forced
conversion and murder are not be any less moral enormities if their
targets are devil worshipers than if they are Episcopalians. A
libelous accusation of devil worship is, however, something religious
people of most persuasions find at least offensive, and the Yazidi
are no exception.
Because a little modestly technical
philosophy is helpful in analyzing the accusation of devil worship,
and is illustrative of turns of argument applicable in many other
settings, I am going to take a closer look at the issue than its
plausibility and the moral standing of the accusers warrant.
Our initial suspicion is that these
charges stem from some not very expert, and even less unbiased,
amateur comparative religion and anthropology. The Yazidi are
monotheists, but the seven spirits, and especially the peacock angel,
Tawûsê
Melek, may get a little more veneration than Christians
traditionally afford angels or saints, excepting, perhaps, Mary. So
it is not completely irresponsible to say that the Yazidi worship
Melek, and I will assume for the sake of argument that they do.
That leaves the question whether Tawûsê
Melek is the devil. There is one conceivable state of reality
in which, I think, the answer to this question would clearly be in
the affirmative. Suppose that the devil really exists. That is,
suppose that there is a rebellious angel, perhaps Lucifer, whose
calling is to cause evil, suffering, and the perdition of souls. The
devil did many of the things ascribed to him in Jewish, Christian,
and Muslim tradition. Moreover, it is the devil that is behind what
is told of Tawûsê
Melek in the Yazidi tradition. That is if we trace the Yazidi
stories about Tawûsê
Melek to their sources, we will always find the devil as their
real world protagonist. Under these circumstances Tawûsê
Melek would be the devil, and the Yazidi should be said to
worship the devil, even if contemporary Yazidi's believe that Tawûsê
Melek is the source of good, not evil. Believing good things
of the devil does not make him any less the devil.
This account of Yazidi devil worship,
in addition to its admittedly extravagant assumptions, depends as
well on a particular theory of the way names hook up with what they
are names of. The theory I used here is due to Kripke, and is called
the “causal theory” of reference. It is an attractive theory for
a number of reasons and in a variety of contexts. It seems true, for
example, that the morning star was the very same star as the evening
star even in that dim prehistory in which everyone would have
regarded “the evening star is the morning star” as trivially
false. Even if a similarly ancient expression for “whale” were
etymologically “big fish that spouts,” what they referred to in
using the expression was a mammal not a fish – assuming that it was
whales and only whales for which they used this expression when they
were looking out to sea.
So, happy to apply the causal theory in
the event of an existing devil, I can see how the Yazidi might be
devil worshipers even if they stoutly and sincerely deny it. (Of
course, on this theory of reference, it is also conceivable that
orthodox Christians might be devil worshipers – on the impious
assumption that it was the devil who is at end of the causal chains
of our use of the word “Jesus.”)
What, however, if, as seems not wholly
improbable, the devil does not exist. For the causal theory, this
would be the case if tracing back the causal chains associated with
the expression “the devil,” we always end up with imagination,
intentional fictionalizing, or pure speculation. It would follow
from this that neither the Yazidi, nor anyone else, ever see the
devil, are possessed by the devil, tempted by the devil or injured by
the devil. It does not, of course, follow that no one believes in the
devil or worships the devil.
To understand belief or worship of
non-existent things, we need to draw upon another theory of
reference, associated with Russell, reference via definite
descriptions. Belief in a non-existent devil would be belief in the
existence of something meeting a certain description, the details of
which would vary across religious traditions. The description that
the Yazidi would give of Tawûsê
Melek would have only the slightest overlap with the description
Christians would give of the devil. There is one striking similarity
between Tawûsê
Melek and the Muslim Shytan, refusing to bow to Adam, but other than
that the two do not seem at all alike. And the Yazidi God regarded
the refusal to bow a demonstration of a proper fealty to the divine
because Tawûsê
Melek himself was an emanation of God whereas Adam was merely made
from dust. Muslims regard Shytan's refusal to bow as the sin of
pride.
Focusing
on this single component in the Shytan and Tawûsê
Melek stories, it was perhaps natural for Muslims of a non-scholarly
and ungenerous caste of mind jump to the conclusion that the Yazidi
are devil worshipers. It seems safe to conclude, however, that even
if the devil exists, the expression “Tawûsê
Melek” is very unlikely to trace back to the devil causally. If the
devil does not exist, no fair minded examination of Yazidi theology
would conclude that Tawûsê
Melek is enough like the devil of Judaism, Christianity, or Islam to
convict the Yazidi of devil worship.
No comments:
Post a Comment