I will not
positively insist that we “see” anything when we close our eyes
in a not bright room. If you prefer to say that we have a “visual
sensations” or something of the sort, that is fine with me. There
is at least something going on that permits us to make such
descriptions as “there was a greenish blob that drifted down and left
above a small, yellowish comma shaped patch.” Nowadays these
experiences, or perhaps more accurately the content of these
experiences, are called, by philosophers, “qualia.” Russell, G.E. Moore and others
in the early 20th century would have called them “sense
data.”
The friends of sense data were aghast when their critics proclaimed that sense data did not exist. What about those closed eye color patches? For those patches, I think we should more or less stick with the friends of sense data. Those patches do exist. We can report on them, and when we do so we use basic color, shape language.
However, sense data critics had the better of the overall argument. Sense data were supposed to be a much wider genus and far more important than our closed eye color patches. They were supposed to be the content of every experience. They were also, and this was of vital importance, the empirical ground floor of science. They were what observation came down to in the end if we were rigorously scientific and hard headed. They were the footings level of a foundationalist empiricism, the indispensable starting point of our knowledge of the world.
There were two properties of sense data
that were supposed to equip them for this all important function.
First, they were immediate experience in that they were right there
on the surface of experience. They were what was in
consciousness when we were having an experience. Second, they were
immediate in the respect that they were not mediated by our prior
beliefs, theories, or biases. It is for this latter reason that they
could function as the uncontroversial starting point for science.
This far, however, we cannot follow the
sense data theorists. The fatal flaw of the theory, as their critics
pointed out with more or less clarity, was that the two kinds of
immediacy come apart. Maybe they don’t come apart for the color
blobs sensations with your eyes closed. Those blobs are what we are
directly conscious of, and they seem minimally affected by our
theories and biases.
With our eyes open, however, we only
rarely see anything like uninterpreted swatches of color. When I look
at a penny from an angle, I don’t see a coppery ellipse; I see a
circular penny at an angle. To try to get back to something like
what the patches on my retina must have been like, I have to perform
mental calculations. I almost always get these calculations wrong in
any complicated scene. Unless you have gone through long hours of
training in perspective drawing or are a spatial genius, you do too.
This point was argued effectively by my teacher Norwood Russell
Hanson. See his Patterns of Discovery.
Optical illusions work because what we
are immediately conscious of is usually highly dependent upon our
prior beliefs, theories, and experiences. What we seem to see here is
one central circle considerably larger than the other.
This comes from
a (usually very useful) processing heuristic in our brains of judging
sizes by their relation to their environment. It is very hard to see
the right central circle as the same size as the left – even after
measuring. Covering up the circumambient circles will do it, and if,
again, you are a spatial visualization whiz, you may be able to do
this in your head.
So if we want the sort of immediacy of
what we actually see it is the immediacy of people, pennies, and
optical illusions as they fool us.That is to say the contents of our
consciousness are almost always highly theory laden. They are not
pure and bias free. Thus they utterly lack the sort of immediacy
that was supposed to make them the uncontroversial starting point for
science.
That there is no such thing as
immaculate perception, as would be pre-theoretic data, is a point that
post-modernism runs with – often to relativistic extremes. I will
not here expatiate on where they go astray, though go astray they
certainly do. The path is long from the theorized nature of all data
to such conclusions as that there is no such thing as objective
truth.
But back to sense data and our closed
eye starting point. Is it right to say that we see sense data when we
close our eyes? The harm of saying that we do is not great and it
would be little worse to say that we experience sense data in a dense
fog or a very dimly lighted room or when first awaking. Even in
these special cases, however, we have to be careful not to go too far
in the direction of sense data theory.
You may be tempted to say that you are
certain or that you couldn't be wrong about what you see with your
eyes closed. It is true that you just experience what you experience
with your eyes closed. There is nothing you could be wrong about, but
for that very reason truth talk and certainty talk are out of place.
It is only when you start describing your experience in terms
of blobs and patches that you first have something to which truth or
falsity and certainty or uncertainty could apply. Yet once you get to
this verbal phrase, can't some error creep in? Couldn't you use the
word “patch” where “curtain” would be more apt? Maybe that
blob actually started to the left of the comma shaped patch and
drifted straight down. It surely isn't impossible that you could get
such a detail wrong. What we see with our eyes closed can be pretty
complicated.
So even the experiences that are most
sense-data-ish, do not have all the properties they were supposed to
have on sense data theory. More important, science clearly does not
start out from the likes of the colors you experience with your eyes
closed or of a dim room upon awakening. Sense data theory, although
it contained a smidgen of truth, is mostly false, and anyone whose
use of “qualia” edges towards sense data theory is going to tend
to mislead us.
No comments:
Post a Comment