A recent case note: “United
States v. Smith, District Court Denies Oxycodone
Distributor's Post-trial Motions in Penalty-Enhancement Case.” 129
Harv. L. Rev. 2297 (June 10, 2016) makes the point that understanding
such statutory language as “result” and “causes” in terms of
“but for” causation runs into a problem with concurrent sufficient
cause cases, what philosophers call “overdetermination.” I want
to take a look at some hypothetical poisoning cases, with
independently sufficient causes, to pursue some issues of
interaction, timing, and the general way to approach hard questions
of criminal causation.
With intent to kill, and knowledge of
efficaciousness, Badone surreptitiously mixes substance A into
Vic’s green tea. Without knowledge of this, Badtoo, with similar
intent and knowledge, puts substance B into the cream that Vic used
with his tea.
Half Hour. Suppose now that Vic
died half an hour after drinking his tea with cream. A doctor on board
declared Vic dead, and said that what he saw was consistent with
poisoning. As it happens that is all we know on that score however.
No autopsy could be performed because Vic’s body was washed off the
deck and lost at sea.
Both Badone and Badtoo, are clearly
guilty of attempted murder. More difficult questions arise for
charges of murder.
Let us imagine a joint trial of the
two on the murder charge. In the real world there would almost
certainly be a trial of one of the two, and then, perhaps the other,
but for our purposes, it is useful to imagine that the liability
question for each is before the same judge and jury.
There is uncontradicted expert
testimony that the dose of A in Vic’s tea would, acting alone, have
killed him in about an hour. B alone would have had the same effect
in 3 hours.
Defense counsel will argue, properly,
that Vic, though young and having recently passed a physical with
flying colors, might have fallen to a stroke, heart attack, arrhythmia, pulmonary embolism, or aneurysm. In their motion at the
end of the prosecution case, defense emphasizes that, absent an
autopsy, there is no evidence directly inconsistent with death
unrelated to the poisons. The judge, however, given the timing and
expert testimony, will let that question go to the jury.
If the jury concludes that Vic was
poisoned, it would, on the present facts, have to convict both Badone
and Badtoo. Because Vic died before either poison acting alone would
have killed him, it must be that it was the combination of A and B
that did him in. It is strongly analogous to the classic bleeding from
two wounds fact pattern, and both malefactors would be liable, even
though they were not acting together.
Two Hours. What now, if Vic had
died two hours after drinking the tea. Here it seems at first glance
as if Badone but not Badtoo could properly be found liable. The most
natural inference is that B must have acted as a partial antidote to
A, somehow slowing up A’s action, perhaps by neutralizing some
fraction of it. At least, in the absence of autopsy, it would
initially seem hard to convict Badtoo on these facts alone.
That is the way I think things would
stand in most such cases. Consider, however, an extraordinary case. A
chemist testifies that A and B mixed in those proportions would form
a new compound, C, a poison intermediate in speed between that of A
and B. It could well lead to death in two hours.
The prosecution contends that this
brings Badtoo’s liability right back, he being equally responsible
for the specific poison that in fact killed Vic. It is no different,
she argues, than if Badone and Badtoo had each procured Vic’s
ingestion of one half the total dose of C. Badtoo’s substance B was
unquestionably a but for cause of Vic’s actual specific death –
when he died and of what he died. Causation is a matter of science,
here physics, chemistry, and physiology, and they show that the
ingestion of B was a direct cause of Vic’s death.
Badtoo's counsel concedes that Badtoo was
part of the causal chain leading to Vic’s death from the point of
view of science, but then so was the person who brewed the green tea,
and all those who designed, manufactured, sold, transported, or
washed, however many times, the tea cup. With only a little
extravagance we might say that everything within the light cone of
Vic’s death was its cause. Legal cause, in order to do the job we
ask of it, must be a good deal narrower than the branching lines of
causation known to science. Perhaps this very inclusive chain of
causation will do for a first “cause in fact” phase of the
causation inquiry, but when we get to “legal cause” we use norms to
draw lines across the chains of scientific causality, excluding what
is too remote, too incidental, too little foreseeable, or otherwise
normatively inappropriate for criminal liability.
Badtoo, his counsel continues, cannot
possibly be considered the cause of Vic’s death, as Vic would have
died a half hour earlier had B had not been in the cream. Slowing
someone’s death is nothing like administering a second wound that
speeds the draining of the victim’s lifeblood. Had Vic been brought
to an emergency room, a doctor with only B relevantly at hand, might
have given Vic a shot of B to prolong his life until the stat call
brought safer antidotes for A and C from across town. Something that
could be used to save Vic’s life, cannot be the legal cause of his
death. Yes Badtoo was the cause of Vic’s actual death, at the
moment he died, but so was the chest pound that kept Vic alive an
extra minute. For Badtoo’s action, Badone’s poisoning of Vic
meets the legal definition of a “superseding cause.” It was no
different than if Vic had been shot before lifting the tea cup with
its poisoned cream to his lips. Indeed, Badtoo’s relation to the
superseding cause is even better than that, because he interfered
with poison A, slowing its fatal action.
Given a chance to rebut, the
prosecution argues that Badtoo, with his intent to kill, is a world
away from an ER doc who might give a patient the same dose of B in an
attempt to save a patient from A poisoning.
The defense responds that Badtoo will
be properly punished by his bad intent by the attempt charge, to
which his client has always been willing to plead in exchange for
dismissal of the top count. Intent cannot be made to do double
service as the key element of attempt and also a surrogate for
causation.
After due thought, the judge announces
that she will not dismiss the murder charge against Badtoo and that
she will charge the jury that a poisoning may be a cause of death if
it contributes to the death even though it acts in an unforeseeable
way together with another poison, so long as death by poison was
reasonably foreseeable. She explains that she thinks that matters of
intent can be relevant to legal causation. It makes a difference that
Badtoo was not an ER doc trying to prolong Vic’s life. Had B acted
only as an antidote to A, Badtoo would not be legally responsible for
Vic’s death. Because B was, however, an ingredient of substance C
that the jury could conclude killed Vic, Badtoo ought not to be able
to take advantage of the incidental circumstance its operation led to
Vic’s living a little longer than he would if only the victim of poison A. Badone’s poison was not a superseding cause that would cut
off Badtoo’s liability because the two poisons were not independent
but combined in their effect.
She might, if she were an exceptionally
scholarly judge, go on as follows, but you may skip this unless you
are as nerdy as she:
My conclusion is consistent with Lawrence Crocker’s definition of
“cause in fact” in “A
Retributive Theory of Criminal Causation,” 5 J.
Contemp. Legal Issues 65, 69-77 (1994). The victim’s death, when
he died, followed by the laws of nature from no set of initial
conditions that did not include both Badone’s and Badtoo’s
pouring of noxious substances into tea or cream. I recognize that
Crocker’s definition also makes it a cause in fact that there was
no hole in the tea cup and that it would make Badtoo’s pouring a
cause in fact even had B been a wholly benign antidote to A.
Whether we patch the definition of cause in fact or take care of it
at the next phase, that of legal causation, does not seem to me to
matter much. If we are to follow tradition in distinguishing these
two phases at all, I suppose it is at the second that we say that
giving B to extend life is separated out from giving B to kill.
Really, however, I think Crocker went altogether too far in endorsing
the traditional distinction between cause in fact and legal cause.
The “common sense” component that separates cause in fact from
purely scientific causation is continuous with the normative elements
of the legal cause analysis. There is no neat division between the
two, and legal cause type considerations have to be brought in for
some problems that would traditionally seemed to raise pure cause in
fact issues. I say this without intending to deny that it is good
practice to start on a causation problem from common sense notions of
causation as deepened by our best science, and then bringing legal
norms to bear.
Three or More Hours. Here,
again, it is clear enough that A and B are in some way interfering
with each other, but still very likely that one or the other or both
together would be on the bad side of the story explaining Vic’s
death.
Let us put aside, for a moment, the
wave that washed Vic’s corpse away and suppose that we can bring
the full resources of science to bear on the question of criminal
liability. Blood toxicity tests and careful examination of organs
might show that B acts only as an antidote to A, unfortunately not in
quite large enough a dose to have neutralized all of A. (No B still
in blood stream; some A; only A-targeted organs compromised.) Badone
should be convicted of murder; Badtoo found guilty only of attempt.
Alternatively, B might be an antidote
to A with enough B left over after neutralizing A to cause death
itself. (No A still in blood stream; some B; only B-targeted organs
compromised.) Badtoo should be convicted of murder: Badone of attempt.
In a middle case, A’s independent
effect is nullified but, either be forming a new compound C or by
other mechanisms, A and B acting together lead to the demise of Vic.
So we are back to the considerations with which the judge had to
wrestle in the two hour case. She would reach the same conclusions,
and we might have a few qualms – B here extended Vic’s life yet longer beyond the baseline
of A poisoning alone.
Science, or more accurately common
sense deepened by science and supplemented in the hard cases by
norms, can settle these cases. What if science has one hand tied
behind it – our yachting no autopsy case? There is always the possibility that
the chemical and physiological interactions of A and B are so well
understood by the experts that evidence can be given, even without
autopsy, to convict Badone, Badtoo, or both. More likely is that
without the corpse we can know with high certainty that one or both
caused Vic’s demise without being able to convict either. The
heart of retributive justice is that we not convict the innocent, and the
reasonable doubt standard makes it inevitable that there will be
cases in which the factually guilty cannot be found legally guilty.
The identical twin hypothetical is the poster child here. The outcome
might be different in a wrongful death action. There is good sense in
placing the financial burden of Vic’s death on Badone and Badtoo
not Vic’s family.
In this particular case we can console
ourselves with the severity of attempted murder sentencing.
Moral of the Story. Science is
the essential first step for criminal causation. Were criminal
jurisprudence only a matter of the wickedness of the accused, we
would not have to be so concerned with the actual mechanism by which
the prohibited effect came about. The law has, however, long been
guided by the principle of retributive justice that those who commit
bad acts are not guilty of as serious an offense if those acts do not
in fact produce the bad effect aimed at. “In fact produce” is
matter of common sense as supplemented by science – the better the
science the better.
Science alone settles the question when
an act can be shown in the particular circumstances to function only
to counteract another act sufficient to cause the prohibited harm (or
otherwise sufficient to do so.) When, however, there is any way in
which both acts contribute to the harm, even if one or both also
partially counteract the other, then science alone will not settle
the question of liability. Normative judgments have to be made
wherever there is positive interaction.
Bleeding from both wounds is
usually enough for liability for both independent assailants. It is
not, enough, however, if one scratched and the other severed the
carotid. It may not even be enough if one’s punch to the nose
caused a serious nose bleed but the other’s scimitar slashes got
carotid, femoral, and brachial. A poison that both delays the effect
of another poison and contributes to the ultimate death is usually
the legal cause of death, as our judge concluded. Perhaps our
responsibility norms however will put it on the no-liability side of
the line if the death is very long postponed or if the science can
tell us, e.g., that 99 out of 100 parts of the B substance acted as
an antidote to A, and only 1 part combined with A towards the death
that would have come only slightly less quickly by the remaining
un-neutralized A alone. Science is always essential; our
responsibility norms sometimes are.
On occasion determination of criminal
cause requires more science than can be brought to bear under the
circumstances. In such cases the guilty will properly be found not
guilty.
Because the interacting poison cases
bear such a close relation to the McLaughlin-Hart-Honore cases of the
independent malicious tamperers with a desert hiker’s water bottle,
I plan to reconsider my previous take on those cases next.
No comments:
Post a Comment