The desert traveler’s water bottle
maliciously tampered with by one malefactor and then stolen by
another has bedeviled the jurisprudence of criminal causation since
1929.
Well, the bedeviltry worked by this problem has been only occasional, not because there has ever been consensus as to its correct resolution, but because the fact pattern doesn't arise so very often in the real world.The inadequacies in our standard formulation of causation brought into the spotlight by the hypothetical have been of much interest only to those of a pathologically theoretical bent. Without pretending to exempt myself from the latter category, I would claim that seeing the water bottle problem in the right way can contribute to an understanding of criminal causation – an understanding that, could it become widespread, might save judges and commentators from some of the false, and sometimes silly, things that they say when addressing the causal leg of criminal liability.
I turn for a second time to the
problem also because I have thought for some time that I got it wrong
in A Retributive Theory of Criminal Causation, 1994 J.
Contemp. Legal Issues 65.
In McLaughlin’s original version,
“Proximate Cause” Harvard L. Rev. 39 149-199 (1929), the first
malefactor puts salt in the water keg. Later, an entirely independent
evil-doer steals said keg from said hiker. The hiker dies of
dehydration in the desert. McLaughlin ends his 3 line footnote
discussion of the case with: “Who killed him?” Hart & Honore,
in a belief that they were preserving the essentials of the case
while make it crisper, have the first bad guy poisoning the water in
the keg. The second, again, steals it. Causation in the Law,
(1985) 239-241.
Water Poisoner. Let us do the
easier issues first. In the Hart & Honore hypothetical, it seems
quite impossible to hold the first malefactor liable for anything
more than attempt. He tried to poison the hiker. The hiker was not
poisoned. When the poison went down the drain, his attempt was foiled
as completely as an attempt ever is.
Salt Thief. Only slightly less
obvious is that the thief in McLaughlin’s version didn’t kill the
hiker. Yes he stole a water keg, but it contained only salt. The
theft is as irrelevant to the hiker’s death as if the thief had purloined a spare sock from the hiker’s pack. Salt is of no more
help in warding off dehydration than is hosiery.
Thief of Slow Acting Poison. If
dissolved in the the keg's water was a poison so slow acting that the
hiker would have lived longer had he had it, rather than nothing, to
drink, then there is little room for doubt that the thief caused his
death. It was the lack of water that cut short his life. That the
water of which the theft deprived him, being poisoned, would not have
gotten him very far makes no difference. If you put a bullet through
the brain of someone trapped in a burning building, it is you who
have killed him, not the arsonist.
Thief of Fast Acting Poison. This
seems to be the case that Hart & Honore had in mind. The thief
was responsible for the hiker's death as he died and when he died in
that the hiker would have died earlier if the thief had not
intervened. Having acted with malign intent, however, the thief is
not automatically exonerated by the clock. (See my 8/29 post for a
little more on this and
Retributive Theory 75-76.)
Yet, as you will shortly see, I now think I was wrong in the article
in concluding that the theft was a legal cause in this fast poison
case.
Yes, the hiker's death was exactly
of the sort the thief had in mind, and he was unquestionably
responsible for the fact that there was no keg in the hiker's
rucksack. This all tempts us into thinking that the thief, in effect, took the
liability onto himself when he substituted his own plan for the (unknown) plan of the poisoner.
We should, however, resist that temptation. The thief is not
responsible for the lack of potable water in the rucksack. That
circumstance was already established before the thief got his hands
on the keg. He stole nothing that could help the hiker survive. His
theft was a mistake, his plan having become, on closer inspection,
impossible. If one is trying to kill by dehydration stealing a keg
of fast poison is as much a failure as stealing a keg of stove fuel. What
killed the hiker is that he left for his hike without potable water,
and the thief contributed to that only in certain possible worlds.
The actual world is the one for which we punish, and in that world
the thief's actions were causally irrelevant.
Defense counsel
might fairly go so far as to argue that, were we to look to
non-actual worlds, in many of them the thief's action would have
saved the hiker altogether. A slightly more conscientious hiker would
double check for water before setting out into the desert. A poisoned
or salted keg would likely pass muster. A missing one would not. This
is no consolation to this particular hiker, of course, but it is of
at least rhetorical force in illuminating the tenuous connection of
the theft to his death.
For the same
reason that one cannot kill a dead person, one cannot kill by theft
of water one who had no water.
Keg Salter. I contended in
“Retributive Theory” that salt substitution was a cause of the
hiker’s death – arguing that the hiker's doom was sealed at that
moment. The hiker died of dehydration in this world, and generally in
any nearby possible world. In the very nearest by of worlds, those
most like reality, the keg is successfully stolen. Slightly more
distant are the worlds in which the thief fails to get his hands on
the keg. In some of these the hiker may have chanced to handle the
un-stolen keg, and, salt being roughly the density of water, failed
to notice that something was different. In all these, the hiker dies
of thirst.
I now think, however, that I was wrong
in the article about the salter too. Whether or not it is right that
in all the appropriately close possible worlds the hiker died dehydrated,
the salt substitution did not kill the hiker. The keg was not there
when the hiker died. That salt was or was not in it at the crucial
moment had nothing to do with the death.
Paradox: Killed by Human Action, but
Killed by No One. So of the six evil doers in the various
versions of the desert dehydration, only one is guilty of murder
because only one, the thief of the water spiked with a slow acting
poison, causes the hiker's death. In McLauglin’s case and in the
fast poison case, no one is guilty of more than attempt. How is this
possible when the hiker was unquestionably done in?
We would have no trouble in finding
both guilty if the malefactors had been acting in concert. “I will
try to put salt (or fast poison) in his water keg, but as backup
when you later get your chance, you try to swipe it. One of us
should succeed, and it’s no problem if we both do.”
Is it not a plausible postulate of
criminal law theory that if the actions of two persons operating
together are the legal cause of a death, then the actions of at least
one of the two must cause the death even if they are operating
independently? If this seems plausible to you, it shouldn’t. Acting
in concert in effect creates a single actor, a fictional, but legally
salient, individual. The actions of the actual co-conspiring persons
are brought together as those of the fictional person and treated as
a single cause. The analogy of this fictional person to
co-conspirators is close enough to assimilate criminal liability of
the fiction to the actual malefactors; for independent perpetrators
it just isn't.
If one thief turns out the lights, and
he and a second unrelated miscreant takes advantage to grab purses and
a watch or two from the cocktail partyers, the prosecution cannot add
the value of what each had when apprehended to make out grand
larceny. If the two had been co-conspirators, that addition would be
perfectly proper.
Co-conspirators who set fires in two
separate parts of the hotel, which ultimately combine to burn it
down, are liable for the entire damage even though neither embryonic
blaze by itself would have burned much of the hotel. (Either
alone was within the capacity of the sprinkler system.) Independent
fire setters who did exactly the same thing would not be liable for
the whole, at least criminally, because neither would be responsible
for the other’s essential contribution to the result.
You may want to say that justice is
better served in that case if both are held criminally responsible
for the whole damage. Consider, however, that the part of the
structure near where A started his fire – the room that was fully destroyed
before the two blazes even joined. B cannot be made liable for that
damage without some very strong principle of the strict liability ("at risk") family that overrides all considerations of causation.
The bleeding from two wounds principle
in the strong form applying to independent inflictors of wounds,
neither of which would be fatal alone, is such a principle. Its
generalization could get us to the fire case, and its aggressive
generalization to these desert hiker cases. These are generalizations
that I think we should abjure.
There is not really any paradox in the
proposition that something caused by human beings, all of whom have
criminal intent, is not caused, for criminal law purposes, by any one
of them. This happens when the causal chain is, for example, too
indirect or unforeseeable, e.g. the voodoo pin sticker who, being
surreptitiously observed by the intended victim, causes such victim,
not previously known to be superstitious, to die of a hear attack. In the hiker
cases the partially conflicting vectors of the malefactors' actions
add up to cause death in a way not foreseeable by either. Our common
sense tell us that together they caused the death, but, as the evil
doers were not acting in concert, a close examination shows that
neither can be held criminally liable for that result.
Still, an aroma of paradox, and the so
prominent role of moral luck in my solution to the hiker problems
will persuade some that the right answer really is liability for all.
Hart and Honore thought that our causation concepts do not apply
well in these conditions, and certainly do not apply to make
poisoning or theft causes in the usual senses. They suggest, however,
the possibility of holding such malefactors guilty of murder as a
matter of policy.
When you poison, salt, or steal water
bottles, and that is part of the whole story that leads to the death
of your intended victim, you should get, some argue, no legal
cover from the fact that other interventions undermined yours. To go
to a theory of criminal causation strong enough to reach this
conclusion, however, would seriously deflate the role of resulting
harm in the criminal law. The badness of the malefactor is
normatively important but so is the harm, where there is harm, and
whether the malefactor can, with justice, be said to have caused it.
Yes, there is a recurring, and popular,
argument that nothing beyond the wickedness of the actor or that of
her immediate intended act should be salient for a rational system of
criminal liability and punishment. This argument would relegate such
language as “causes the death of such person or of a third person”
to the bad old days in which a superstitious society barely sublimated its primitive passion for revenge.
My own view is that the resulting harm
component of the law has always been there and will continue to be
there for a very good reason. A death really is worse than a close
call. For Macbeth and Hamlet we honor Shakespeare, not because
Marlowe or Bacon lacked the genius, insight, or energy to have
written these plays, but because of the happenstance that the quill
that penned them was in the hand of Shakespeare.Who actually caused
a result makes a difference to such creatures as we.
No comments:
Post a Comment