Saturday, July 8, 2023

Rights and the 2nd Amendment

In an old blog post I argued that the Second Amendment created three constitutional rights.  “One is a right to participate in the military, in Latin jus militiae, from its origin in Roman law. The second is a right to possess weapons for the purpose of the participation in the militia, [now the National Guard] guaranteed by the first right. The third is a broader right to possess weapons unrelated to matters military.” The Second Amendment: Not One or Two but Three Rights  I was mistaken.

No right to carry weapons

What I did not, and still do not, think is protected by the amendment is the right to carry weapons, whether open or concealed, except as reasonably incidental to the right to keep weapons. “Bear arms” is all about the militia.

“Arms” by itself has, and had in the late 18th century, a strong military aroma. Kitchen knives could be “weapons” but hardly “arms.” Revolutionary war “arms” included canons, muskets, rifles (few, non-standardized), grenades (lighted fuse), helmets (few), tomahawks, swords, and bayonets (standard for British fewer for Americans.)

To “bear” is and was to display, carry, or endure. It was a word not often used except in special contexts, usually conveying some sort of seriousness or solemnity. “Bore the medal,” “bore the uniform,” “bore the casket,” bore the sorrow.” “Bear the salt to the table” would be uttered only if levity were afoot. To say “he bore a tomahawk home” would be understood, but aberrant, at best.

The seriousness, of “bear” made it particularly fitting to be joined with “arms” to form the phrase “bear arms” meaning to participate in a military or quasi-military or to engage in military hostilities.

Scalia insists, against the detailed discussion of historical linguists submitted as a friend of the court brief in District of Columbia v. Heller (2008), that “’bear arms’ means, as we think, simply the carrying of arms:” Scalia attempts to refute the linguists’ long list of founder period instances of “bear arms” meaning military participation. This he calls  the “idiomatic meaning.” He contends that “Every example given by petitioners’ amici for the idiomatic meaning of “bear arms” from the founding period either includes the preposition “against” or is not clearly idiomatic.” He did not include in his opinion these “not clearly” military cases, so that we could make a judgment whether to agree with his judgment or that of the linguists.

There is a handful of instances in the Heller opinion’s tenth footnote, alleged to be uses of  “bear arms” meaning “carry weapons.” Two instances were over a century before the drafting of the amendment, not exactly the founding period. Three were of Scottish or Irish provenance. (Scottish English seems particularly likely to differ from American or even English usage, especially for “bear.”) There is no American or even English example in the footnote within the generation of the First Congress. Indeed, only one was from this continent at all.

That one, a Kentucky commentary on the Second Amendment, does not use the word “carry” or any synonym. Instead, it states that the amendment does not protect from a criminal charge those “who exercise this right in such a manner, as to terrify people unnecessarily.” A Kentucky prosecutor would surely have cited this commentary in defense of criminal charges against a militia detachment or gang of rogue militiaman for burning down the homes of native American “squatters” on the frontier. No weapon need be involved.

Scalia’s equating the “bear arms” to “carry arms,” is strongly contrary to the evidence as to the way “bear arms” was used in 1791. “She decided not to bear arms home because they were too heavy” or “Please bear arms on our walk by the river this evening” would have been at least as bizarre then as they are now. “Carry arms,” which for Scalia equates to “carry weapons” would be an implausible reading of the amendment’s “bear arms,” even absent “A well regulated Militia, being necessary to the security of a free State” in the presence of that ablative absolute preface, it is impossible.

Therefore, Bruen vs New York State Rifle & Pistol Ass'ny (2022) was wrongly decided. The amendment does not constitutionalize a general individual right to carry weapons around.

Jus miltia

The overwhelmingly more common meaning, if not in fact the only extant meaning, of “the right to bear arms” in 1791 American English was the jus militia (of Roman law) –right of participation in a military organization. That it was worth the effort to recognize this as a right may be surprising today. Couldn’t anybody join the army or navy or the Virginia militia, or almost anybody? Memory at that time, however, ran back to the history of private militias and, in particular, to the Trained Bands of England, open to membership only for those who shared the politics of the organizer. Participation was to be a right of the people not only of some people. (We know, of course, that few of the southern Congressmen and ratifiers thought those of African descent to be full-fledged Constitutional people.) The proposals and early drafts, by exempting conscientious objectors from militia service (Quakers, anabaptists), make it clear that “bear arms” was about the right of militia participation (and the fear that the right would morph into a duty, even for the objectors.) (For details see the “To bear Arms” subsection of section 1 of The Second Amendment: Not One or Two but Three Rights (lawrencecrocker.blogspot.com))

Not only could one carry weapons without bearing arms, one could bear arms without carrying a weapon. (Even the Continental Army had clerks.)

Possession

What I am have second thoughts about is the general (not militia related) right to keep weapons. My defense of this was based on the speculation that most of the ratifiers would have understood “the right of the people to keep and bear Arms as giving them the right to keep weapons whether or not they had anything to do with their state’s militia.

I still think this was probably the expectation of many of the ratifiers and possibly even some Congress members. I did not face head on the fact that whatever expectations of this sort there may have been were the result of misreadings of the text. A risk of legislatively enacting written documents is that some of those doing the enacting may think that the text says something other than what it does say.

Democratic theory mandates that only the meaning of the enacted text matters, not the expectations or intentions of those whose votes turned it into law. Intentions and expectations are often difficult to extract from the historical record. An individual’s expectations and intentions may be vague and are certain to be incomplete. Two legislators, both voting “aye” may, may have very different, even contradictory expectations. The evidentiary problems with intentions and expectations are not the key point, however. The key point is that intentions and expectations were not voted upon and turned into law. Only the text was.

If it were “. . .right of the people to keep arms . . . “

If the words “and bear” were absent”, the amendment would, indeed, have been best interpreted as constitutionalizing a general, individual right to keep weapons. The word “arms” would have been badly chosen, but that sort of thing happens in hasty redrafting before an upcoming vote in Congress. On this thought experiment, the here would be two different rights to keep weapons by dint of the militia prefatory clause. For those militia eligible by age, gender, fitness, (race), there would be a presumption giving constitutional protection to some combat-appropriate weapons: muskets, maybe rifles (parts and training problems), conceivably grenades, certainly not canons, as specified by reasonable muster orders. This possession right of the militia eligible, would be than the right of the of the general population. Delaware might have banned possession of bayonets except for the militia eligible, but all would have a right to a fowling piece.

Factoring in “bear arms”

That “arms” was part of an indissoluble two-word phrase focused on the militia makes it a little harder to read “keep” as a general individual right to possess weapons. We can understand when a word is pulled out of an indissoluble phrase to serve a second and different function, but it is grammatically odd. Consider: “He killed time, the bottle and three mosquitoes.” You would not be shocked if I told you Mark Twain wrote this, although, as a matter of fact, he didn’t. Scalia’s example is, “He filled and kicked the bucket.” These are modestly humorous precisely because they play fast and loose with semantic/syntactic rules.  

Scalia’s “carry weapons” interpretation avoids the problem but at the cost of reading the militia clause out of the amendment, ignoring that it is “arms” not “weapons,” and, as just discussed, running contrary to the usage evidence, the experts, and the draft history.

Let’s look at three possible readings:

          S:  People have a right to possess weapons and to carry weapons around.

M: People have a right to join the militia and to keep arms appropriate for that purpose.

C: People have a right to join the militia and to keep arms appropriate for that purpose and people have a right to keep weapons.

(Scalia, Militia, Combined, as having elements of both M and S.)

When “bear arms” is interpreted as it must be, S drops out as a possibility. That leaves us with some level of syntactic/semantic incongruity with respect to the Janus-like function of “arms.”

Phrases, especially elegant phrases that roll off the tongue, can acquire immunity to critical examination in the course of the drafting process. The Conventioneers and the First Congress seem to have been susceptible to this infirmity. In addition to “keep and bear arms,” we have “high crimes and misdemeanors,” “respecting the establishment of religion,” “a capital, or otherwise infamous crime,” “cruel and unusual punishment.” These, among other sonorous phrases of the Constitution, have led to disproportionate interpretational conflict down the years.

That a nice phrase might bend syntax/semantics a tad ought not be shocking. It is telling that “bearing arms” was used in proposals and drafts for what became the Second Amendment that were unquestionably militia centered and where “bearing arms” certainly did not mean carrying weapons around. In concatenating “keep” with “bear arms,” framers doubtless thought that everyone would understand, even if the new phrase played a little fast and loose with grammar.

It is important, however, that M is less fast and loose playing than is C. This is among the reasons that I now conclude that M is the better reading, even though I continue to suspect that the drafting probably led some ratifiers to believe that it established a general individual right to possess weapons.

The Anti-dead-hand principle

I am also positively influenced by the fact that M is weaker than C and far weaker than S. So M loosens the dead hand’s grip on legislation centuries later.

A committed democrat is required, at least as a first approximation, to prefer among plausible readings, that interpretation of an entrenched constitution that least restricts future democracy.

(There may be an exception for principles so fundamental that they properly could be imposed on even the most democratic of democracies by brute force. The 13th Amendment is a paradigm candidate. Even these exceptions should not be read to make them the best they can be, but only good enough that nothing better should be imposed upon the democracy by said brute force. See the last several paragraphs of  Jefferson Davis and the Moral Right to Abolish Slavery (lawrencecrocker.blogspot.com)

The Right

A good deal of the Bruen reasoning turns on “the right” of the Second Amendment, which the Court says is to be elucidated by looking to “the Nation's historical tradition of firearm regulation.” This is a slight reworking of Scalia’s favorite way of putting his finger on the scales when the text didn’t give him quite the answer he wanted. Scalia’s phrase was “traditions of the American people.”

I have not confirmed that the Boston ordinance against possession of a loaded firearm in the city was still on the books as of 1791. The slave codes of the southern, and some not so southern states at the time the Second Amendment was ratified prohibited a substantial percentage of the people from keeping arms. (How would Congress have voted on the Second Amendment had, say Madison, argued that “the people whose keeping of arms is guaranteed by this Amendment are all the people, whether counted in the census as five fifths or three fifths”?)

Safety

One thing that is clear about the rights set forth in the Bill thereof was that they were inherently limited by considerations of justice and safety. There was in 1789 no law on the subject so far as I know, but the Supreme Court was surely correct many years later in arguing that the First Amendment’s “freedom of speech” did not extend to protecting the shouting of “fire” in a crowded theater.

We know that even the current Supreme Court, doubtless the most NRA-friendly Court ever, must recognize that safety considerations constrain “the right of the people to keep and bear arms.” Had there been no law prior to 1939 within “Nation's historical tradition” against throwing explosives, I yet doubt that the Court would so much as deign to hear a challenge to the National Firearm Act (of that year) as applied to prohibit the possession of hand grenades.

Normative expressions

Taking safety into account in delineating the Second Amendment right brings front and center an interpretive principle that I think of crucial importance, a principle that may seem to conflict with the anti-dead-hand principle. It focuses on provisions containing clearly normative words and phrases: “reasonable,” “cruel and unusual,” “due process,” “right.’

My contention here is straightforward. For example, the due process clauses of the 5th and 14th Amendments do not constitutionalize all and only the process that was thought to be due in 1791 or 1868. The framers could have been written “due process as traditionally understood” or added a sentence “Due process requires . . .”  But they didn’t. The text mandates due process, and the judiciary’s task is therefore to determine, as best it can, what process really is due.

This can lead to results wildly different from those of originalism understood in terms of framer or ratifier intentions or expectations, or “the Nation's historical tradition” but it follows directly and necessarily from the axiom that the original meaning of the text controls. To take the text seriously is to take normative words as normative, not as disguised descriptions of the beliefs of forebearers or framers or of a tradition. The members of the First Congress would have thought capital punishment not cruel and unusual for a wide range of offenses including horse stealing. Probably the majority, however, would have thought it cruel and unusual to lock someone up for ten years. Tradition.

Textualism rigorously understood then has some resemblance to “growing” or “living” constitution theories. If the Court determines that due process requires more than it once was thought to, then the Constitution may look as if it is changing. The Justices, however, will typically say that this is what the text required all along. Opinions written in this fashion are at least purporting to use the right interpretive method. (Whether they really are is another matter.) So, this understanding of normative words and phrases in the Constitution does have some potential to loosen the grip of the dead hand.

(The grip is shifted, however, not to Congress, but to the unelected federal judiciary, which may or may not instantiate best values. Whatever it does, it does not do it democratically. That is the system we are stuck with, however, having an entrenched constitution and strong judicial review.)

The resolution of any apparent conflict between the two principles, anti-dead-hand and taking normative provisions normatively, is that the latter is lexically prior. If taking the normative word or phrase seriously requires interpretation a and rules out interpretation b, then, then b is not a candidate for the final interpretation, even if it is less restrictive of future democracy. The anti-dead-hand principle only breaks ties. It does not overcome the meaning of clear text.

If there were a general, individual right to possess weapons

Even on the Court’s view that there is a general, individual, private right to keep weapons, the militia prefatory clause makes it perfectly clear that this general right is less stringent than the special right of the militia eligible who might be required to muster with their own weapons. In today’s world that might possibly constitutionalize the possession of assault rifles or shoulder fired rockets by such individuals.

However, pursuant to laws and regulations governing units of the National Guard and its predecessors, there have not been any bring-your-own-guns militia members for over two hundred years. So, on the mistaken view that the Second Amendment constitutionalizes an individual right to keep, and even to carry, weapons, it is still inconceivable that it would override reasonable safety considerations or would void statutes prohibiting possession of weapons of mass slaughter. See Conjectures & Arguments, Philosophy & Law: The 2nd Amendment Right to the Open Carry of Swords and Shoulder Launched Missiles .

Other posts on the 2nd, not referenced above, which I still stand by, mostly: The Purpose of the Second Amendment Failed Long Since (lawrencecrocker.blogspot.com);  The 2nd Amendment Right to the Open Carry of Swords and Shoulder Launched Missiles (lawrencecrocker.blogspot.com) Guns don’t kill people, true -- in exactly the same way ricin and hand grenades don’t kill people. (lawrencecrocker.blogspot.com)

No comments:

Post a Comment