Should those who call themselves “libertarians” object to people contracting themselves into slavery? If so, are they right?
I forgive you for thinking that this is a stupid question. Isn’t libertarianism about maximizing liberty, and slavery the antithesis of liberty? Yes and no. Ordinary language would suggest that libertarianism should indeed be about increasing liberty, constrained only by the most pressing claims of other values. Slaves had very limited choice sets for the direction of their lives and day by day. An increase in the choice sets of each and every person is a chef goal of some us who think of ourselves as libertarians. We, however, often need to use such phrases as “left libertarian” or “positive libertarian,” or “opportunities libertarian” to distinguish ourselves from those who are now commonly called “libertarians.”
This libertarianism is not at all about maximizing or
increasing liberty. More nearly it is about minimizing human, especially state,
interference with certain favored liberties. (For much more on this see my book
Positive Liberty.)
Libertarians, I concede, denounce chattel slavery as in the antebellum US. Being a South Carolina slave was the result of a kidnapping or of having a slave mother who had been kidnapped or whose mother’s mother had been kidnapped . . . Kidnapping is one of the sorts of infringements on the freedom of movement that libertarians universally condemn. So, this sort of slavery is out.
You might project that libertarians must be staunch enemies of
any and all forms of slavery? Not so fast.
Libertarians tend to believe that their relationship to
their own living body is one of ownership and generally think of this particular
ownership right as inalienable. Their property theory of personal rights seriously
understates the normative relation between persons and their bodies. (See Conjectures &
Arguments, Philosophy & Law: April 2016 (lawrencecrocker.blogspot.com).
Perhaps the wrongheaded property metaphysics of some libertarians does hide the
cyst of a pro-slavery bacillus. I will not, however, involve us in those issues
here. Instead, I will assume that no libertarian would believe that one can
literally own another person.
Someone who thinks that resort to dictionaries can
decisively settle disputes about moral and political values might say at this
point that my charge against the libertarians must be dismissed because slavery,
by definition, is a matter of ownership – of having a legally cognizable
property right in the slave. The evidence bearing on this meaning claim would
be muddled at best in that a great deal that is called “slavery” does not
involve legal ownership. In any event, my contention is that it is possible to
produce a state of affairs that includes what we most hate about slavery
without the slave’s being the master’s property.
Slavery, I concede, requires an extreme contract, but it
could be, I argue, a contract consonant with libertarian theory. The right to
enter into contracts, and in particular the right to enter into labor
contracts, has always been a key libertarian right. Coercive contracts are
void, but libertarians do not typically count a labor contract as coercive
merely because signing on was the only way the worker could prevent her family
from starving. One of the most obvious characteristics of libertarians is a
great generosity towards rich and powerful contracting parties on issues of
contract formation and the validity of dubiously conscionable terms. (Some libertarians would recognize the
invalidity of a “take it or starve” contract if the employer were responsible
for the threat of starvation in a sufficiently direct way.) Fraudulent labor contracts
are, of course void, but, again, libertarians tend to be very sparing in
finding materiality in falsehoods uttered by moneyed side in negotiations.
What I want you to consider is a labor contract that not
even the most tender hearted would consider coercive and that in which the
person selling his labor has full knowledge of everything that any reasonable
person would think material to deciding whether to enter the contract. It is
the model of a contract freely entered into and for that reason into it would
not fall out of libertarian favor because of the number of hours of labor per
day or the number of days per year or the number of years, or indeed of the
perpetuity of the contract. (If your imaginations strains at this task, put
that aside for now. It will be addressed in my final paragraphs.)
Slavery, of course, is more than onerous labor. The master
has a right to tell the slave where to be, what to do, and what not to do not
just when actively working for the master but at every moment of every day. Assume,
however, that the slave is not ordered to do anything that a libertarian would
regard as actually criminal or tortious. The whole business, of course, might
well be unlawful under laws libertarians consider illegitimate, e.g. those
governing wages and hours, safety, and the like, but that would not make it
libertarian-invalid.
With these crime/tort exceptions, I don’t see how the
libertarian can object to any detail of the contract so long as it is genuinely
freely entered into and, recall again, that libertarians are not at all
demanding when it comes to this voluntariness condition. I have never heard of
libertarian objections to the practices of even the most rigorously of
regulated monastic orders, so long as the monks or nuns had full knowledge in
advance of what they were getting into – a condition typically supposed to be satisfied by a
novitiate period.
That the contract permits the master to punish the worker,
even corporally, need be no problem. Libertarians believe that the prohibition
against assault can be contracted around. Think of heart surgery, of ultimate
fighting, and of consensual sadomasochism. If voluntary contracting does not
extend to permission for the application of bull whip to ditch digger’s back,
we need an explanation why not.
So almost all of conduct of the 1840 Mississippi slave owner
towards the field hands can be contractually sanctified pursuant to libertarian
contract doctrine (excluding only the masters’ rights over the children of
slaves.)
Will the libertarian support for contractual slavery stop
when it comes to state enforcement? It would depend, I think, on the kind of
enforcement. The libertarian would have no problem awarding damages under
standard contract theory if the slave breached the contract and walked away. I
do not anticipate that the libertarian would become squeamish if the court ordered
a garnishment of the ex-slave’s future income that would leave her living on a
shoestring.
Where the libertarian would draw the line, I think, would be
at criminal proceedings or mandatory injunctions to hold the slave to his
bargain. Here we, again, return to the definitional objection. I can almost hear a libertarian chorus: “Only
the state can create slavery. No fugitive slave law, no slavery.” (It is something like the libertarian claim
that if only the state would keep its hands off the economy, there would be no
monopolies.) They might suggest, instead of “slaves,” “perpetual omni-service
workers.”
That it should make all the difference in the world to
liberty whether the voluntarily enslaved absconder is brought back by the
sheriff or by a private security firm would be just one of the consequences of the
insistence on certain definitions by libertarianism that, I hope, strikes you
as paradoxical.
In any event, those who would abscond in breach of their contracts
might well be recovered without state action. The master might ride them down
by horse or ATV before they had left his land. The rights of property for the
libertarian, are easily strong enough to support the validity of that term in
the contract. Indeed, I see no reason the libertarian would balk at a term that
would permit private persons to effect a forcible recovery anywhere. Bounty
hunters would be a possibility. Alternatively, an association of masters might
fund a private recovery force. Just put permission to be apprehended by such
into the contract.
Private recovery of absconders might be every bit as
effective or more effective than state enforcement of a fugitive slave law. Libertarians
might still resist calling it “slavery” harkening back to the fundamentals of
their understanding of liberty. It is
not important for liberty, as they theorize it, what a person can choose to do.
There is no loss of liberty unless a person is prevented by the state or another person from doing what she
has a right to do. Having voluntarily agreed to be apprehended by private
persons upon absconding, the bounty hunters infringe no right of hers. There is
no violation of contract, and for that reason there is no debit of liberty and
no slavery. Assuming the voluntariness
of the contract, it’s all fine.
Here, again I hear a libertarian voice. This time it is
almost screaming:
Your assumption that such a contract could possibly be
voluntary is nuts. You convict us of theoretical support for what you are
pleased to call “slavery” by foisting on your readers an utterly farcical
hypothetical. You ignore the fact that free markets, unimpeded by the
interference of the state, will never leave workers truly destitute. If you had
any understanding of the economics of a libertarian society you would know the
impossibility of your imagined “voluntary” accession to a contract of, what we
agree, would look something like slavery.
If they were correct in this, it would be a fair, though
only a partial, objection. The libertarians would not be at the slightest risk
of actually sanctioning contracts of the sort I imagine. Still, the thought
experiment would show something important about the underlying values of right
libertarianism.
The “utter impossibility” accusation, in any event, is overstated.
That there cannot be desperate poverty except as the result of state action is
a theorem of economic models based on stunning oversimplifications and breathtakingly
naïve assumptions. Real world evidence is strongly to the contrary.
Moreover, it is not necessarily only the dangerously poor
who might enter into one of these slavery contracts. Those with very highly
remunerated talents, which talents have limited half lives, might do so as
well. The basketball player or operatic soprano might conceivably sign such a contract
for a huge upfront payment, one purpose of which would be to raise immediately
and dramatically the living standard of family members. The prudent athlete or
diva would also squirrel away a large nest egg for later purposes as will emerge.
The master during the life of the contract, of course,
collects all of what the star would otherwise have earned. The contracted-out
slave was not so uncommon before the Civil War, especially in Virginia. Neither
the basketball player nor soprano would have to worry about being sent out to
dig ditches. To keep their market value up their masters will have to be
careful of their training, health, and psychic wellbeing. When the Achilles
tendon ruptures or the voice fails, the slave might well just buy out the
contract. This should be possible at a reasonable figure as the income stream
that was the master’s motivation in contracting will have all but dried up. Even
under US chattel slavery some few slaves were able to buy themselves out of
slavery. Unless and until they are able to buy out their contracts, however, contract-based
slaves remain slaves.
Our basketball player and soprano might be able to achieve
all their goals in entering into a slavery contract through such alternatives
as loans, insurance, more exotic financial instruments, or some combination
thereof. Perhaps. Still the occasional soprano or ball player might choose the slavery
contract for reasons well or poorly thought out. The libertarian should have no objection, and
that, I think, is a sign that their values and understanding of liberty are
askew.
Any voluntary choice that does no impermissible harm to others has moral weight. But when a choice, however voluntary, would alienate a great part of the person’s universe of future choices, ending their autonomy, a society really concerned with liberty would hold it void. Slavery by contract would be slavery, and unacceptable to real libertarians, whatever those who usually call themselves "libertarians" might think or, without thinking, be committed to by their fundamental doctrines.
No comments:
Post a Comment