G.E. Moore was the Professor of
Philosophy at Cambridge in the early twentieth century when Cambridge was the
center of the philosophical universe. Fellow Cantabrigians included Alfred
North Whitehead, Bertrand (the 3rd Earl of) Russell (one of only a trio of
philosopher winners of the Nobel Prize for Literature, the others being Camus
and Sartre), and Ludwig Wittgenstein, later Moore’s successor in the
Professorship.
The Moore thesis for today is that
it is better that a Beautiful World (hereinafter “BW”) exist, even if so
distant that no one will ever see it. In this Moore was trying to refute
ethical hedonism, as then expounded by utilitarian theorists, who claimed that
the good (what is valuable in a way relevant for morality) is exhausted by desirable
states of consciousness. Henry Sidgwick, the most prominent of these theorists,
specifically contended that there could be no value in any beauty apart from
its contemplation by conscious beings. [Methods
of Ethics, book I, ch. IX, s. IV, pr. II, p.114).]
Moore:
Let us imagine one world exceedingly beautiful. Imagine it
as beautiful as you can; put into it whatever on this earth you most
admire—mountains, rivers, the sea; trees, and sunsets, stars and moon. Imagine
these all combined in the most exquisite proportions, so that no one thing jars
against another, but each contributes to increase the beauty of the whole. And
then imagine the ugliest world you can possibly conceive. . . . The only thing
we are not entitled to imagine is that any human being ever has or ever, by any
possibility, can, live in either, can ever see and enjoy the beauty of the one
or hate the foulness of the other. Well, even so, supposing them quite apart
from any possible contemplation by human beings; still, is it irrational to
hold that it is better that the beautiful world should exist, than the one
which is ugly? Would it not be well, in any case, to do what we could to
produce it rather than the other? Certainly I cannot help thinking that it
would . . . [Principia Ethica, Sec 50.]
Sharing Moore’s intuition, I told class
after class of students that I would be willing to kick in a couple of dollars
towards the existence of the BW. My students thought I was nuts.
Student: I don’t get why you should
care whether the BW exists. Are you thinking that some non-human observer, maybe
space aliens, angels, or God might see the BW?
LC: No, that would be cheating. Although
Moore expressly veils the BW only from “contemplation by human beings,” I take
his underlying position to be that no perception of any sort by any being is
required for the BW to be valuable.
Student: How about an autonomous
space-drone flies by, probes the BW, and draws from it higher order aesthetic
principles that it incorporates into the architecture of a public building of
an alien people?
LC: Still cheating. The BW I think
is to have value without having any effect at all, direct or indirect, upon any
consciousness.
Student: So I guess you are just
pro-BW as a matter of your personal preference structure. You can like haggis,
rose wine in a box, and round squares for all we care.
LC: My personal preferences are
immaterial. What I am claiming, following Moore, is that it would be an
objectively better universe if it included the BW. It would be more valuable with
respect to the kind of value that we all should care about.
Student: Then you are kidding
yourself. My diagnosis is that you are imagining, in contributing your two
dollars, performing a selfless act, for which you congratulate yourself. Or, because
you’re a philosophy professor you further ennoble it as a “community-of-conscious-beings-less
act.”
LC: Except that I concluded that the
BW would be valuable first, and only penciled the $2 into my outline to
emphasize the point for any of you whose attention at this time of morning
might still be dulled by the effects of last night’s fraternity parties. Of
course the BW could never really be the object of public subscription. Moore
had tongue firmly pressed against cheek in asking whether it would “not be
well, in any case, to do what we could to produce it?” He conceded that it
would be “highly improbable, not to say impossible” that we could have any
actual choice about the BW’s existence. The claim is simply that the BW would
be intrinsically valuable. The hypothetical of doing something towards its
existence is only a device for focusing the discussion.
Student: OK, but I still think it’s
all in your head. Moore sketches a picture for you. The image that arises in
your mind is beautiful and so it is
valuable – as is, the $2 aside, what I still suspect is you get a kick out of
being a fanboy of esoteric entities.
LC: But I do have a clear intuition
that the BW itself would be valuable. I can certainly separate out the (very
slight) value of my vague image of the BW. I have images in my mind of Laocoön and His Sons. But, even though I
spent some time walking around that sculpture in the Vatican Museum, my memory
images are foggy. The value of the sculpture itself is orders of magnitude
greater than the value of what is in my mind. Were you right about my
narcissistic self-congratulation in upholding the value of the BW, that would
be even more easily separable from the value of the BW.
Student: The reason I think your
intuition is, in fact, contaminated by what you mistakenly believe you can
separate out is that I don’t see how something can be valuable at all if it
doesn’t have any relation to beings that are valuing. Are you claiming that if
there never was or would be consciousness, still a universe with a BW would be
more valuable than one without?
LC: Plato would have said so. For
him beauty was an objective feature of reality valuable because of the relation
of the form of beauty to the form of the good. The value of a beautiful object,
independent of appreciation of its beauty, is easy on that theory.
Student: If your intuition has it
that the BW is intrinsically good, surely it is a big good. It’s a whole
planet! Why then would you be willing to pay only a measly $2 to bring it into
existence?
LC: Well, Moore was even cheaper. He
imagined making a choice (hypothetical remember) between the existence of the
BW and an ugly world if absolutely nothing else turned on it. In effect, he only
committed himself to the modest claim that if it were costless it would be
rational to call the BW into existence. I’ll concede that the BW gets a
discount for its inaccessibility.
Student: I’d say it should be a “100%-off
sale,” but on the Platonic theory the BW shouldn’t get any discount at all. It’s
its closeness to the good that
counts, not closeness to us, wandering around in this world of mere shadows of
the really real. Anyway I can’t believe
you want to rest your BW claim on Platonism. Won’t you admit that morality and
what counts as value for morality are human constructs, answering to our
specific individual, cultural, or species interests and purposes?
LC: I’ll go along with you that
value and morality are in some sense “constructed,” although that word as used
by post-modernists may be more trouble than it is worth. Let’s just agree that
we are using “constructed” in a very capacious sense to recognize the humanness
of value and morality and to exclude at least the full strength versions of
Platonism, divine command theory, and the like.
Student: What if we were talking
about something delicious instead of something beautiful? I don’t have to
resort to goodies on distant planets. Suppose I make my best triple chocolate
cake for a friend who is coming to visit. The deliciousness of this cake, I humbly
submit, would be at least as widely acknowledged as the beauty of Moore’s
mountains and moons. However, the friend doesn’t come. The low life! I smash
the cake, pour vinegar on the mess, and throw it into the garbage. No one ever
tasted that delicious cake. Was it better that its deliciousness existed? Was
there more value to the world because of it?
LC: Well, in the period between
baking and the vinegaring there was one more delicious thing in the world, but
I am not sure that made it a better world except in ways that Sidgwick’s theory
could easily absorb. Hedonism can lay full claim to your pleasant anticipation
of the cake and your friend’s visit. So there does seem to me to be a
difference between your cake and the BW.
Student: It can’t be the difference
between the beautiful and the delicious that makes a difference. One appeals to
one sense, the other to others. That’s all. What I think is that Moore suckered
you in with the romantic grandeur of the beautiful planet shtick. Suppose on a
lonely ocean beach the surf threw together what you would regard as a beautiful
arrangement of driftwood and seaweed. If you had been there you would have said
“Wow” and reached for your camera. But you weren’t there. No one else was either, and the next wave
washed it away. Was there more value in the world because of that beauty for
those few seconds?
LC: It’s a better world where there
is such ephemeral beauty, at least in that each of them has some probability,
even if a small probability, of being seen and appreciated.
Student: But that doesn’t help Moore
against Sidgwick. Moore ruled out any “possible contemplation” of the BW, and
even the smallest probability implies possibility. If the best you can say for
the beachscape is it had some probability of conscious appreciation, then your defense
of your intuition is Sidgwickian not Moore-ish .
LC: OK, yes, for your cake and your seaweed
I guess my intuitions are like yours. Their deliciousness and beauty, if they have
no probability of affecting any consciousness, are not valuable. So I admit that
there is conflict among my intuitions. But my intuition about Moore’s BW is
stronger than my intuitions about your cases. As I take the BW to be highly
supportive of the proposition that some states of affairs are valuable even if
they never have any effect upon any consciousness, I can simply revise my
intuitions in your cases. The cake and seaweed are valuable. My initial
intuitions, I now see, were erroneous in that they are not consistent with the
best theory of value. It’s an exercise in the method of “reflective
equilibrium” as Rawls describes it, as I hope you remember from last semester.
Student: Wasn’t the revision of an
intuition to reach reflective equilibrium supposed to take place if the errant
intuitions were inconsistent with a well-considered moral theory? What is your well-considered
theory that implies that the BW, my cake, and ephemeral surf scene are all valuable?
LC: Well the theory starts out from
the inherent connection between beauty (or deliciousness) and value. You have
no problem with the idea of unperceived beauty, so because the connection is so
close, you should have no problem with unperceived value either.
Student: I am accepting unseen
beauty for the sake of the argument. It is not on me to commit either way on
the noislessness or noisiness of Bishop Berkeley’s tree falling in the lonely forest.
Moore and you both recognize it’s an additional step to conclude from the BW’s
beauty to its making the universe a better place. Moore gives us only his “cannot
help thinking” in support of that step and you haven’t yet helped him out with
a supporting theory. By admitting contrary “initial” intuitions that had to be
reconciled, you are in even more need of a theory than was Moore.
LC: The theory I was starting to
sketch, before your interruption, is that our construction of value for
purposes of morality is very like our construction of beauty. They are so much
alike, that the never to be perceived value is no more impossible than never to
be perceived beauty.
Student: In what ways are they alike?
LC: You’ll grant, won’t you, that
they are both positive sorts of constructions?
Student: Usually.
LC: And that “valuable” has the
wider scope, in that beautiful, delicious, pleasant and the like are all
valuable, at least usually valuable to stick with your reservation. In any
event, there must be some significant overlap between the construction of
beautiful and that of valuable.
Student: Some overlap, but that the
beautiful is only usually valuable is
important. If everything beautiful were valuable, you and Moore would win
automatically. But a naked eye view of an eclipse may be beautiful and a poisoned
cake may be delicious.
LC: Right, even for constructions
closely aligned, the more specific doesn’t always overlap the more general as
neatly as “square” overlaps “rectangle.” Still, there may be an “in the main”
overlap. You accept, don’t you, that other things being equal what is beautiful
is valuable?
Student: Yes, but that “other things
being equal” is crucial.
LC: The clause excludes your
dangerous beauties and delicious poisons, and more generally, many things that
are a mixture of good and bad. But there is nothing like an associated pain or
other evil for the BW.
Student: So is your theory that the
short lived seaweed and driftwood scene, and every beauty everywhere and at any
time is valuable for the concept of value relevant to morality so long as it is
uncontaminated by any serious negative value?
LC: That’s it, at least roughly. I
would add, to borrow lawyers’ language, that anything beautiful starts out with
a presumption of valuableness, and, unless that presumption is rebutted, must
be valuable full stop.
Student: I think it’s more a bald
claim than a theory. In any event, I have two objections, one from the side of
beauty; one from the side of morality.
LC: Fire away.
Student: First beauty: You have
already, in effect, conceded that the ultimate touchstone of beauty is that an
observer would regard the object as beautiful. What I wonder about is who the
observer is to be. I was bothered by Moore’s PR job for the BW. Don’t you find
it suspicious that Moore describes the details of the BW in terms that cry out
“modern European tourists’ idea of beauty.” You can’t tell me that every
culture at every time agreed on what “the most exquisite proportions” of moon
to mountain would be, and I’m sure some people think mountains are scary and
ugly.
LC: You misunderstand Moore. His
argument doesn’t depend upon everyone’s accepting the mountains-sunsets-stars
paradigm of beauty. Look again at the text. He asked his reader to “Imagine it
as beautiful as you can; put into it
whatever on this earth you most
admire.” So the mountains and stars were merely examples.
Student: So Moore is a relativist
about value?
LC: Better to say Moore was a
partial relativist. Too much arguing about relativism of value and much too
much about relativism in morally has been simple-mindedly binary. Moore would concede,
I think, that there are individual differences and cultural differences for
beauty and other components of the good, but within a universal theme. The
differences come from different biographies or cultural histories, the
commonness from shared genetics, shared environment in the large, and shared
parts of the cultural past.
Student: So some people might think
the BW beautiful and others not. Where does that leave the question whether it
would be right (hypothetically) to bring it into existence? Are you giving up
on your “objectively better universe” claim?
LC: I think Moore would probably
follow Sidgwick and sum up the preferences, but that is beside his point here.
Just take the population who agree that the BW is beautiful. That population should
join me in making that hypothetical contribution towards the existence of the
BW. This Moore would assert and Sidgwick deny. It is an objective question
these two would fight about: whether there can be morally relevant value
without an effect on consciousness.
Student: Then I will focus on
Moore’s European tourist subgroup. Even for their notion of beauty, something beautiful
but never to be seen, does not even begin to be equal to Mt Fuji. It is visual
appreciation that ties the beauty into value. Take away the appreciation and
what is good about it? The number 6 isn’t beauty-valuable in that it cannot be
visually appreciated. A never-to-be-perceived object is other things unequal
where it counts, and so not valuable.
LC: 6 is mathematically attractive
in a couple of ways certainly isn’t visually beautiful, but that is because it
is not of the right ontological type. Wrong category things are very different
from the BW, which is only unperceived in practice. The BW might be the
inspiration for volumes of image filled poetry in some other possible worlds.
Student: I obviously have no problem
with the value of the BW in a possible world where lots of people view its scenery
every day. That something is good in another possible world doesn’t make it
good in this one. I just don’t understand your saying “only unperceived in practice.” Unperceived is unperceived, and the
unperceived beauty has its connection to value broken. The catalogue of all the
beautiful things of zero probability of ever being perceived would not be of much
aesthetic interest. It would not be of any interest at all “in practice,” which
leads me to my second objection, one from the side of moral value as part of
the human practice of morality.
LC: Have at it.
Student: Isn’t morality a practical
business, about what is the right thing to do?
LC: That’s a conception of morality, one with which Moore and Sidgwick would
agree, but there are other conceptions that would, for example, emphasize not doing
wrong things, or doing the right thing for the right reasons, or developing a virtuous character.
Student: Even the virtuous character
theorists would say that the person of virtuous character acts well, correct?
LC: That’s fair enough, so long as
the emphasis is put in the right place.
Student: Well, the telling thing against
the thesis that the BW is good is that it doesn’t make any possible difference
for any action. You admit that there is nobody you can pay towards the
existence of the BW, and there is no other way its existence or non-existence
will affect anybody’s action. Therefore, what you and Moore call the BW’s
“good” or “value” cannot be “good” or “value” for morality, certainly not for
morality as Moore and Sidgwick conceived it.
LC: But Moore’s thesis that the BW
is valuable does lead to conceptual clarification and to fruitful discussions
about value and morality.
Student: Fallacy alert! If there is any conceptual clarification, it comes
from seeing why Moore’s thesis is wrong. That value is the product of the concept of a BW, not of the BW. The concept of the greatest prime number is
valuable for the proof that there is no greatest prime number. And if you think our discussion of the BW has
been valuable, you’ll have to wait for our class evaluation forms to see.
LC: Calm down. I was joking.
Student: But that alleged joke was
as close as you have gotten towards a theory that would support revising your
initial and sensible intuitions about uneaten cakes and ephemeral beach scenes
to bring them into line with your and Moore’s weird views about never perceived
planets. So, without your promised theory, your attempt at reflective
equilibrium fails, and Sidgwick and hedonism win the day.
LC: Even were I to concede so much,
you would have won only a battle for hedonism, not the war. For additional
anti-hedonism see Nozick’s description of the “experience machine” in Anarchy, State, and Utopia, and my
argument that we desire really to be loved or really to accomplish things more
than we desire the perfect counterfeit. (Analysis,
“Egoistic Hedonism,” Vol. 36, No. 4 (Jun., 1976), pp. 168-176.)
Student: So have you at least given
up on the BW?
LC: I see that we are out of time. For
Wednesday please read . . .
No comments:
Post a Comment