In
this second installment of the adventures of shipwrecked Libertarian Bob and Left
Libertarian Ann somewhere in the south seas.
Bob:
Isle Two, for which I am opting, offers
in comparison to Isle One, fewer chances
for jam sessions, fewer books, less art, fewer competitions, fewer get-togethers, and will have me working harder for the same number of
calories. Bad luck for me. I am tempted
to say that this whole hypothetical situation is rigged against hypothetical me
– Isle One being preferable in every respect except that its majority have
imposed upon the unwilling as well as the willing a 5 hour per week public
works requirement. So, I am going to paddle to Two because liberty should always
trump goodies. In any sound political theory individual rights are lexically
prior to other sorts of values, and principles. We cannot violate an individual
right no matter how good the consequences.
Ann:
What individual rights do you
have in mind?
Bob:
For this discussion, the chief right I
have in mind is the right not to be interfered with in what I do by force or
threats of force.
Ann:
Why is the right against interference
by force a side constraint and lexically prior to other moral and political
considerations? What is your support for the very strong proposition that such
individual rights as that against forcible interference always trump everything
else?
Bob:
The starting point is that each human
being is an individual. “Individuals have rights,” as reads the first sentence
of Nozick’s book. [Anarchy, State, and Utopia, p. ix] Does anybody disagree? Isn’t it fundamental that no one can violate another
individual’s rights?
Ann:
There may be some important ambiguity
and vagueness in your principle, but there is a plausible principle in there
somewhere. Suitably understood I think that everyone would endorse it as an
“other things being equal” principle. My problem is that other things often
aren’t equal, and they certainly aren’t on these islands.
Isle One expands opportunities for all at the cost, I assume for argument, of some sort of penalty on anyone who wouldn’t otherwise want to do the five hours of labor that has produced and continues to produce that opportunity expansion. If the scheme falls to a lexically prior, side constraint principle, it will do so no matter how mild and intuitively reasonable is the coercion and how great its benefit. It is this that you need to support. The fact that we are all individuals doesn’t do it by itself.
Isle One expands opportunities for all at the cost, I assume for argument, of some sort of penalty on anyone who wouldn’t otherwise want to do the five hours of labor that has produced and continues to produce that opportunity expansion. If the scheme falls to a lexically prior, side constraint principle, it will do so no matter how mild and intuitively reasonable is the coercion and how great its benefit. It is this that you need to support. The fact that we are all individuals doesn’t do it by itself.
Bob:
Your “all” for which opportunities are
expanded doesn’t exist. Only individuals exist. This tree isn’t me and you
aren’t me. I end at the outside of my skin. It is because of the fact that
individuals are unique, separate, and basic that it violates a primary right
for others to force their will on any individual.
Because reality is like this we all
accept that your right to wave your arms around stops at my nose, and that I,
not you, decide how long I wear my hair, what clothes I wear, and whether I
walk south or north on the beach.
Ann:
Are you really going to base your moral
political principles on this metaphysics?
Only individuals exist; couples don’t exist, triplets don’t exist,
quartets don’t exist, the electoral college doesn’t exist? Incidentally, I can
rephrase the specific use of “all” to which you object as “for each resident of
Isle One, his or her opportunities have been expanded . . . .” I here assume, for purposes of argument, that
at least one One would prefer no labor requirement even at the cost of the benefits
it creates, but that it has expanded opportunities even for these hypothetical
negative votes is just a fact.
Your skin reference also leaves me
cold. Right, there is an anatomical respect in which I end at the outer layer
of my skin. It is not entirely irrelevant to me as a person, however, that I am
looking at an island a mile away, hearing your voice, and smelling the sea air
or that I care about and do things with and for other people and other people
care about me, cooperate with me, and do things for me.
My right to wave my arms around
actually stops well short of your nose (civil assault, menacing). Hair length
we are now pretty easy about, but this was not always the case, and no society
gives the individual carte blanche on
dress (public indecency), and even where you walk in public has some
restrictions (stalking). Our shared
intuitions are a good deal more complex than you suggest, and once those
complexities are explored, I think any support you claim from them for your
brand of libertarianism will drop dramatically.
Bob:
There is nothing exotic about my
metaphysics. Of course quartets exist for certain purposes, but they are also
reducible to their four individual members. There is no quartet mind. If one of
those members hates the Whiffinpoof Song, it will violate his rights for the
other three to force him into singing it with them. We do have shared intuition about cases like
this that show that individuals and their rights are fundamental for moral and
political purposes.
Ann:
Quartets are reducible for some
purposes to their four individuals, whether something isn’t always lost is
another matter. Putting that aside, a
human being is reducible to brain, liver, and the rest, and the brain to
neurons, and so on. Moral principles don’t apply to molecules or neurons at
all, and matters normative come into play in different ways for individuals,
groups, and societies. So reducibility alone
gets you nowhere.
More promising is the way you use it to
motivate the veto of the Whiffinpoof Song. It seems to me, however, that how
strongly the other three want to sing about Morey’s would have some moral
relevance. There might be even more significance in whether the four were
singing in front of a Yale or a Harvard alumni function.
I don’t think you would deny that the
other three can coerce the reluctant one by various means from raised eyebrows
to mockery to kicking him out of the quartet. That any of these might sometimes
be proper shows that there is no side constraint against these forms of
coercion, at least.
Bob:
Each of the other three singers has his
own rights to make facial gestures, mock, or, assuming no contractual
impediments, separate from the anti-Whiff. When there is no right on the other
side, however, then there is a right that has the status of a side constraint
and is lexically prior. They can’t
threaten to beat him to make him sing the song with him.
Ann:
Can they push him onto the stage after
the introduction to the song has been played?
Bob:
Pushing someone onto the stage is I
think sort of play-violence. It is all in fun, and no serious resistance is
expected. If there is serious resistance, then an escalation of the force would
violate a right.
Ann:
There are going to be interesting cases
of shoving on stage someplace north of play-violence, but south of serious
violence. Instead of going into those cases, however, let’s suppose that it is really
important for some reason to the other three to sing the song. One of them
threatens the recalcitrant with two stiff punches to the shoulder if he doesn’t
sing it with them.
Bob:
Sometimes this might fall into the same
category as pushing the guy on stage, especially if there were a history of
shoulder slugging in the group. However, using real force in this scenario
would always be an impermissible rights violation, and so would threatening it.
Ann:
Well, in the case I have in mind the
victim doesn’t want to be hit in the shoulder even once. He doesn’t expect any
lasting harm, but it hurts. He would avoid it if reasonably possible, although
he doesn’t think it is a huge deal.
Bob:
In that case I think it is a rights
violation. It is not the most awful rights violation in the world, and if I
were the anti-Whiff, I might go along and sing the damn song, but I would think
that my rights were violated, and I would hold it against the others.
Ann:
You would not necessarily quit the
group over it though. Isn’t this because the other benefits of being in the
group would outweigh the rights violation?
Bob:
I might not quit the group despite the
rights violation. What I will resist is that it is properly described as the
violation being outweighed by other considerations.
Ann:
Let me pose a couple of scenarios
closer to our current shipwrecked circumstances. Suppose everyone else on Isle
One disappeared save you and one rough chap who required you to get him a
coconut every couple of weeks or so, he being heights adverse. That coconut
would cost you only a minute’s easy climbing.
Another one: the people are back and
the world is just as it is except that the Isle One Assembly has voted only an
hour of labor every year, not 5 hours a week.
Bob:
Maybe neither would really start me
paddling towards Isle Two. At least neither would if the One Assembly promised,
cross-their-hearts-and-hope-to-die, never to increase the work requirement or
introduce any other significant coercive measure. In your alone-with-bully case
I would need some reason to believe that the acrophobe wouldn’t become more
demanding or otherwise behave so as to cause me ongoing anxiety for my safety.
Ann:
Don’t all these cases show that the
sort of individual rights violation we are talking about is not lexically prior
to every other sort of consideration and that it is not a side constraint?
Bob:
No. In the two Island cases, I can say that
my right has the strong properties I contend for, but that I simply can waive
it. It is my right, and I can agree to
forego it where the benefits to me are sufficient.
Ann:
You could do that as well in our “real
world” case of 5 hours of required work per week on Isle One.
Bob:
Yes, but in the 5 hours a week case,
the rights violation is just too oppressive. If I thought it were in my own
personal interest, still, I could not endorse so large scale and systematic a
violation of individual liberty. Even if it happened that no one voted against
the work requirement, the next time it came up, someone might oppose it. The
possibility that that one One would be forced to do a significant amount of
forced labor, is enough reason for me to take a firm stand against the whole
practice.
In the one hour a year case, my staying
on the island may evidence nothing more than my own weakness of the will. In acceding to this systematic but modest
violation, I am ratifying, after a fashion, a politically impermissible
situation. As it is in my interest, however, I might let the principle slide.
It would be a blot, if a smallish one, on my moral character.
Ann:
In saying it would be only a small blot
you are already conceding something. If rights violations are true side
constraints, then there is no conceptual room for discriminating moral blot
size. You may feel worse about the consequences of one violation than you do
about those of another, but all violations are impermissible, end of story.
I think your moral common sense steers
you away in spelled out cases from judgments so black and white. Your self-deprecating
weakness of the will hypothesis is only cover.
Bob:
Perhaps I should admit that there may be a de minimus exception to the side constraint status of individual
rights, an exception within which the shoulder puncher, coconut bully, and one
labor hour per year legislators all fit. These may all be too insignificant. They are rights violations below the moral cognizance line or are not full-fledged rights violations at all. This is the other side of Nozick's “catastrophe override,” where he considers the possibility that a right might be violated if doing so were the sole means of preventing a great disaster.
Ann:
You are cheapening Nozick’s catastrophe
override quite a bit, but I don’t think we should have been too impressed even
by the original article.
Something “de minimus” in law is something so insignificant as to be
outweighed by the court costs of taking it up. To say that there is a de minimus exception to a side
constraint is exactly to say that sometimes other factors outweigh the right,
but that is just what is ruled out by the logic of side constraints. For a true
side constraint other factors are always irrelevant. Once exceptions are
admitted to a principle it becomes, not a side constraint, but at most a
principle of great weight, perhaps such weight that it can be overcome by other
considerations only in rare circumstances.
Your admissions show, in addition, that
there are exceptions where the considerations favoring the violation of the
right need not be especially strong, because the individual right in question
is not a particularly evil rights violation.
The threat of a couple of blows to the shoulder as coercion for a couple
of minutes of singing is just not a big deal. So, despite the fact that it is a
really truly rights violation it is pretty easily outweighed. Similarly, whatever the specifics of the
coercion, a few trips up easy trees, or an hour of required labor in a year,
though violating the rights of the one forced into it, are not enough to give
up the benefits of Isle One over Isle Two. The benefits outweigh the costs,
including any moral principles that might auger the other way. The individual
rights do not trump everything else.
Bob:
I think you have the conceptual
framework here all wrong. I say that there is a line between rights that are
side constraints, and things that look like rights but are below the threshold
for side constraint status. There may be some arbitrariness, or at least room
for reasonable disagreement, in the line drawing, but there are clear cases of
rights above the line – that we should all recognize as side constraints and
that political theory should treat as lexically prior to other considerations.
Line drawing, sometimes pretty
arbitrary, has to be done in any moral system. It is everywhere in the law, and
although advocates often base an attack based on the arbitrariness of a particular
line, we all know that line drawing is necessary, and that some arbitrariness
is inevitable. The difference between a
misdemeanor assault and a felony assault is typically the seriousness of the
injury. Whatever the verbal formulation of the statute, exactly where the line
gets drawn will be arbitrary. Yet the distinction between misdemeanor and
felony assault is not crumbling away in either theory or practice.
Ann:
In the criminal assault case, the
seriousness of the injury doesn’t suddenly become irrelevant when we cross the
boundary from misdemeanor to felony assault. There is usually at least two
degrees of felony assault based upon the seriousness of the physical
injury. The exact location of the lines is
arbitrary, but that seriousness of the injury caused is relevant to the
seriousness of the offense is always in play.
What your admissions show is something
similar with respect to coercion and the rights against it. The seriousness of
the force used or threatened, the distance between what one is coerced into
doing and what one would choose to do, and the importance of expected
consequences on each side you would describe as going to whether a purported
right against coercion in a particular case has side constraint status. I would describe falling on what you call the
side constraint side of the line is simply making the judgment that an other-things-equal
right is, after looking at the other things, a right in fact -- to be honored
in this case.
My objection to your side constraint,
lexical priority, theory is not that it draws lines arbitrarily, but that it
characterizes that status of what is above the line in a way that is
inconsistent with what goes into drawing the line.
Bob:
Your whole attack is based on a few
made up examples where rights violations are insignificant or there are very
significant beneficial consequences of the violation. This just distracts from
all the important cases for which are intuitions support side constraint status
for the right against coercion.
Ann:
Actually, I think that many and common
real world cases of physical or coercive interference with action that are not
clearly wrong. A very incomplete list of
examples would include: typical pushing in crowds, moderately aggressive auto
driving, interrupting in a small conversation, giving a child a time out. Although sometimes each of these is wrong, it
doesn’t take much to lift a particular instance out of that category. The
person who pushes into a subway car as it is closing to avoid being late for
work, again, has been rude, and should no doubt have left home earlier. It would be extravagant, however, to say that
his squeezing into the car was morally wrong.
It is, again, not unlike assault. There are many more misdemeanor
assaults than felony assaults, and many more physical altercations that do not
rise to the level of a crime than misdemeanor assaults.
Bob:
Even if you were right about side
constraint status and lexical priority as a conceptual matter, the big
difference between us would remain. You seem not to appreciate how serious are
physical interferences with and threats against an individual’s doing what he
chooses. In many cases, and particularly in cases crucial to political theory, these evils completely swamp all other
considerations, and are far worse as a matter of both moral and political
theory than other ways in which we lose alternatives for choice.
Ann:
I would like to see in more detail just
what it is about this one sort of way my choice options may be curtailed that is
so supposed to be so much worse than other ways I might lose the same options.
That discussion, was recorded in August of 2017, but somehow disappeared from the blogosphere. Insofar as it could be reconstructed it appears here:
https://lawrencecrocker.blogspot.com/2019/02/libertarian-island-iii-coercion-and.html
https://lawrencecrocker.blogspot.com/2019/02/libertarian-island-iii-coercion-and.html
No comments:
Post a Comment