It has been said that all rights we
have as human beings are rooted in individual self-ownership. If
taken literally, and not as some sort of metaphor, this cannot be
right.
Some talk suggesting self-ownership is
the source of rights might be nothing more than rhetorical flourish,
elaborating the observation that we have rights with respect, e.g.,
to our hands that are, in many respects, at least as strong as our
rights with respect to our gloves. That I will not dispute. I here
take issue only with those, perhaps few in number, who have been
carried away and truly embrace the theory that the fundamental basis
of individual rights is a property right of self-ownership
Property based rights talk is mostly
engaged in by right-libertarians: those who tend to believe that
taxation is slavery; that markets are an unmixed blessing; that
inequality in bargaining position never weakens the moral force of
agreements; and that the externalization of enterprise costs to the
general society is trifling. Secretly many also tend to think that a
free market in public officials is not such a bad thing – if there
must be public officials in the first place.
As you might detect, I am not
altogether sympathetic to right-libertarianism. I do not even show
them the courtesy of using its advocates' self-awarded moniker as –
sans phrase “libertarians.” That is because I think that
they have, from the ground up, a defective understanding of liberty.
I am not, however, from here on out,
going to go after right libertarianism. What I will argue, instead,
is that even the right-libertarian should reject the self ownership
theory of rights. There are far less vulnerable ways to enunciate a
right-libertarian position. (A good place to start is Nozick's
Anarchy, State, and Utopia.)
Property is not the right sort of
thing to be the font of our fundamental individual rights: As
every first year law student learns, property is not a concept set in
stone. Property ownership is a “bundle” of rights and duties, a
bundle that varies from place to place and from time to time. If this
is so, then self ownership cannot be the source of immutable
individual rights, because, first, it itself is mutable. Second, and
of more theoretical importance, self ownership cannot be the
fundamental source of rights, because it itself is constituted, in
part, by rights.
So to make the heroic attempt to base
all rights on self ownership, the first thing one would need would be
a concept of property that is absolute, because not varying in content
across societies, and primitive, because not depending upon pre-existing
concepts of rights.
Absolute property is crazy: It
might be thought that “absolute property” fulfills these
desiderata. An absolute property right gives the possessor the right
to exclude any and all from the property under any and all
circumstances and to do any and all things with the property.
Absolute property has one small problem, however. As Nozick notes,
putting it in your back is not among the many things I should be
allowed to do with my knife.
Maximum property is
definition-defective: A potential solution to the knife in back
problem is to retreat from absolute property to maximum property with
some such formula as “so complete a dominion over one's property
as is compatible with a like dominion over their property by others.”
The problem with this and similar formulations is the “incompatible”
and the “like.” After all, my putting my knife into your back is
not incompatible with your putting your knife into my back. It is
your maximizing your back rights that is inconsistent with my
maximizing my knife rights. It is obvious enough that knife rights
should give way to back rights, but a great deal more is therein involved
than is straight forwardly covered by “like dominion” and
“compatible.”
One beach goer's property right in his
or her top, in particular the choice of wearing or removing same,
conflicts with another beach goer's right to movement of owned head,
eyes and eyelids. On almost all US beaches “like dominion” over
eyes is understood to give way to male property rights over tops but
to dominate female property rights over tops. On European beaches
there is more variability in the resolution of this particular
property right conflict.
The idea that there is some grand a
priori notion of maximal dominion over property compatible with a
like dominion over others in their property is an illusion. Instead,
conflicts of interests and rights have to be resolved by concepts
that go deeper into the human condition than does the concept of
ownership. Nozick went deeper by drawing upon Kant's ideas of human
autonomy, and the non-use of others. He also gave a passing nod to
the concept of the meaning of a human life. The current generation of
right-libertarians would do well to take seriously both his arguments
and his intimations.
Rights without property: There
can be rights without anything that looks much like property.
Consider the possible immaterial world in which five souls can do
nothing but think and communicate with each other by an immaterial
version of talking. (If you are concerned that they would have
nothing to talk about, you may assume that they have an immaterial
app for browsing the internet.) We can imagine that the right not to
be interrupted might be recognized by these five, and that such
underlying concepts as equal respect would animate whatever
principles emerged for regulating their conversations. I suppose
that the origination of novel ideas might give rise to something like
intellectual property. (“Doesn't Alice deserve the credit for first
recognizing that the continuum hypothesis is flatly false?”)
Still, there cannot be more than a wisp of property in this
hypothetical world, but could well be clear rights.
Other-ownership: We have a model of ownership of persons close at hand: chattel slavery as it existed in the United States. The owner was another rather than the first person self, and this, of course, makes a great difference. Still, it is precisely the contrast between slavery and self ownership that gives the latter concept its rhetorical force. Self ownership is the repatriation of the property model from the outside to the inside.
Even though other-owned, the slave had
a few rights (though very few), varying from state to state. The slaveholder's rights
over the slave did not extend as far as his rights over his boots or
even quite as far, usually, as his rights over his horse. This, by
itself, shows that ownership cannot be the root of all individual
rights, as even those without self-ownership had some rights.
On the other side, there were rights
that neither the owner nor the slave possessed. Even working jointly
the slave and master could not qualify the slave to be a citizen, a
juror, vote, attend school, and so on and on. Ownership can protect
the owned property from some sorts of insults but is not proof
against others. An important set of rights may plausibly be
associated with ownership, but as not all rights. Therefore, again,
self-ownership cannot be the fundamental source of rights.
Alienability: One
of the paradigmatic features of property is its alienability. Indeed,
there were jurisprudents, in the bad old days of unguarded
essentialism, who went so far as to say that alienability was an
essential feature of property. We would not now say that. Still,
inalienability counts against the aptness of saying that your
relation to yourself is that you are your own property. Slaves could
be alienated, but since the 13th
amendment no one resident in the US or subject to its jurisdiction
can sell himself or herself.
Animal rights: Only
humans and such artificial legal persons as corporations own
property. Your dog, whatever she may think about her food bowl,
cannot own property. Therefore, on a self-ownership model of rights,
it is quite impossible that your dog or even the unowned bobcat of my
neighborhood woods should have any rights at all.
Mind-body metaphysics:
The idea that the body is owned by the mind or soul is only going to
be appealing on fairly strong theories of mind body independence.
Then, however, it is not so much self-ownership as the self owning a
separate thing – the body. It is worth noting that on some
theistic traditions the individual soul does not really own the body;
God does. The soul has the body on a kind of long term lease.
On most theories
of selfhood, it is more attractive to say that it is self identity
rather than body ownership or self ownership that is metaphysically
primary.
Commoditization: For
right-libertarians the greatest of all historical villains is Karl
Marx. Marx predicted that with the advance of capitalism human
beings and the relations among human beings would more and more be
reduced to property relations. Now some right-libertarians would have
it that a property relation is at the center of human rights. Ironic?
Marx would not be surprised.
Ideological drift:
Right-libertarianism at its
most attractive has seen property and free markets as means to the
realization of human freedom. Its vision of freedom may be cramped,
but it is genuinely concerned that human choices not be shut down in
certain sorts of ways. Placing property and ownership in the center
of focus risks a slide in emphasis. At its worst, instead of
capitalism as a means to human freedom, humans become merely an input
to capitalism.
It is to have
one's heart sort of in the right place to advocate capitalism on the
(doubtless mistaken) understanding that it is a requirement of human
freedom. When capitalism itself comes to be seen as a high value,
there follows a tendency to celebrate lavish consumption and even
greed. That some go to bed hungry and sick is not an evil to be
addressed, nor even a regrettable but inevitable concomitant of the
way things ought to be, but instead exactly the way things ought to be.
It is certainly possible to hold the theory that rights flow from
our self-ownership without going to this extreme, but property as
the core concept of political theory tends to make easy the Rand-y
path.
No comments:
Post a Comment