I have been reading, or rather
listening to (free librivox.org) “The Rise and Fall of the
Confederate States of America,” written by the president of that
ill-starred nation. You will not be surprised to hear that Davis
writes with a bias that shines forth from nearly every
paragraph. You may be surprised to hear that he is an intelligent,
acute, well informed, and occasionally persuasive constitutional
analyst.
The first place that the bias shows up
is in the early made and frequently repeated refrain that secession
was not about race or slavery, but about northern tyranny in the
affairs of the south. With this claim front and center, this reader
was a little surprised to find out that over 95% of the grievances
discussed by Davis in his account of what led up to secession are
directly about slavery, its exclusion from some of the western
territories and states, failures to return fugitive slaves, and
anti-slavery agitation by northern abolitionists. The remaining 5%
concern tariffs, trade policy, and other economic issues not directly
involving slavery, although having strong indirect ties.
Those who wish to rewrite civil war
history to make it center on something other than slavery will find a
well spoken ally in Jefferson Davis, but they will be embarrassed by
the evidence favoring the other side found page after page in the
history he penned.
What did Davis think of the morality of
slavery? Mostly he avoided the question, relying upon the evasion
that the Constitution had put the issue of morality beyond debate,
having recognized the institution in its three fifths of a person
clause and having given it protection in the fugitive slave clause.
So far as one can tell from the book, which is perhaps not very far,
Davis was a middle of the road racist by the standards of his day. He said that the slaves were of an "inferior race." His
preferred language for southern slavery was “African servitude,”
but it was clearly more a matter of color than of continent. There
can be little doubt Davis would have more qualms about holding a
light skinned Algerian than a sub-Saharan in slavery. That the
Constitution of the Confederacy protected the institution of “negro
slavery” everywhere, including new states and territories, makes it
clear enough that race was key for Davis and his colleagues. It also
underscores how important slavery was in a document that otherwise
altered the US Constitution only to give states more rights.
He fully endorsed the view, apparently held by many southern preachers, that the slaves were better off than they had been in Africa. Servitude to their well-meaning owners provided them with productive labor, adequate subsistence, and favored them with the truths of the Christian religion.
In the second volume, it is clear than nothing angered Davis as much, as a violation of the rights of the people of the southern states, as did the emancipation ordinances. That union forces recruited and armed former slaves made him nearly apoplectic. The chief right of the people that he complains was trampled by the northern tyranny was the right to own slaves and when he talks about the destruction of southern institutions by the invader, it is always slavery that is uppermost in his mind.
He fully endorsed the view, apparently held by many southern preachers, that the slaves were better off than they had been in Africa. Servitude to their well-meaning owners provided them with productive labor, adequate subsistence, and favored them with the truths of the Christian religion.
In the second volume, it is clear than nothing angered Davis as much, as a violation of the rights of the people of the southern states, as did the emancipation ordinances. That union forces recruited and armed former slaves made him nearly apoplectic. The chief right of the people that he complains was trampled by the northern tyranny was the right to own slaves and when he talks about the destruction of southern institutions by the invader, it is always slavery that is uppermost in his mind.
Davis made the central constitutional
issue the right of states to secede for any reason or no reason, and
on this point he has persuasive, if not decisive, arguments. There
being, today, no serious secession movement in the United States, the
right of secession is of constitutional interest primarily as it
bears on the question whether a state has a right of nullification –
declaring federal law void within its territory. The argument goes
that if a state has a right to secede, which would be to nullify all
federal law, it must have the lesser right to nullify particular
laws. This, of course, does not follow. Even were there a right to
secession, the Constitution might be an all or nothing deal. The
Supremacy Clause suggests it is at least that. It would make no
sense to make federal law the supreme law of the land, and then give
each state the right to nullify federal law as it chose. If I read
him right, Davis, despite being a strong advocate of the
constitutional right of secession, was lukewarm at best on
nullification.
Davis's arguments on the nature of what
was created by the Constitution are weaker than his arguments on the
right of secession. He does not want to grant much (if anything) in the way of
sovereignty to the federal entity. He understands sovereignty to lie
ultimately in the people, and he argues strenuously that even after
the adoption of the Constitution there was no such thing as the
people of the United States. There were only the people of
Mississippi, Massachusetts, and the other states. (Not included, clearly, in his "consent of the people" arguments were the slaves.)
Davis's interpretation on this point is
made more difficult by the very first phrase of the Constitution, “We the People of the United States.” It does not read “We
the People of each of the ratifying states” or even as the
Constitution of the Confederacy has it “We,
the People of the Confederated
States, each State acting in its sovereign and independent character.” This latter formulation
does at least suggest that there might be no people of the
Confederate States, as such, because the people acted through and the
individual states and hence, for things touching on sovereignty, are
people only of those states.
“The
people” appears five times in the Bill of Rights. The natural
interpretation in each case is that it is the people of the United
States, in their direct relation to the United States, that is
referred to, not the people of the states or the people of the states
merely added together. The right of the people “peaceably to
assemble and petition the Government,” for example, is facially a
right that each of us has as a citizen of the United States.
Alaskans and Alabamans don't have to assemble separately or sign
separate petitions. Davis my not have liked it, but the US
Constitution did, even if that of the Confederacy nominally did not,
create a new level of peoplehood, citizenship, and sovereignty. The
relation of federal sovereignty to state sovereignty is, of course, a
complexity giving rise to perennial issues.
The
fact that the Constitution did create a sovereign entity and a United
States citizenship would complicate Davis's secession argument. The
right of a state to secede would carry with it the right of the state to
extinguish the United States citizenship of the people of that state.
The anti-secessionists of South Carolina, even those who were white,
had their US citizenship stripped from them unless they emigrated to
a northern state (or joined the Union Army as did many blacks and and
a few whites.) In creating a United States citizenship, did the
Constitution implicitly leave it a prerogative of a state on its own
initiative to take that citizenship away? Could that be consistent
with the Supremacy Clause?
Let
me put all such issues aside, and assume for the sake of argument
that Davis was right about the constitutional right of secession.
Other things being equal, then, Lincoln would have had no right to
use force to reverse the sessions of the various southern states. The
“preserve the union” rhetoric would not suffice, and the
“rebellion” rhetoric would be wholly inapt.
Other
things, however, were not equal. The confederated states were slave
states. The niceties of sovereignty and state self determination
might arguably have to give way when they shield the systematic
institutionalization of the most egregious possible denial of
individual self determination and liberty.
Davis
speaks a good deal of liberty, and saw the armies of the Confederacy
as engaged in a war for liberty. The liberty of the slaveholders to
do what they would with their property ranked high among those
liberties to be protected against northern tyranny.
We,
of course, strike a very different balance between the liberty of the
slave and the property rights and liberties of the slaveholder. What
I am going to argue is that the balance is so different that
otherwise illegitimate force may morally be used against slavery.
Take
yourself in a time machine back to the antebellum south and equip
yourself with some very powerful weapon, garnered, perhaps, by
running your time machine in the opposite direction. Suppose that
your weapon will inflict severe pain lasting for several hours on its
targets. It is a weapon after the tradition of a smart bomb only very
much smarter. It is so smart that it can be programmed to target all
and only slave owners. Well, it may miss some, but it will have
almost no false positives. You also have, from the same source, a
device that turns ordinary air into a loudspeaker. This permits you
to speak to the entire south at one time. Using this device, you
give the warning that unless all slaves are released within a week,
all persons remaining with slaves in their possession will be subject
to agonizing attacks of whole body pain.
We
can anticipate, I think, that some very few slaves might be freed
immediately after the warning, the very occurrence of which would
have been regarded as either miraculous or demoniacal. In fact, if
you prefer serious deception and blasphemy to physical intimidation
and torture, you might announce through your universal broadcasting
device that you were God and that you commanded a freeing of all the
slaves. (In addition to its dishonesty, this expedient has the
disadvantage that a fair majority of the southern clergy would
probably be prepared to argue that the message could not possibly be
from God because the Bible was unambiguously pro-slavery. The message
must really be from the devil, or from those disciples of the devil
called “abolitionists.”)
Disbelief
in your threat would, in any event, be widespread despite the
unaccountable nature of its delivery. After the first day on which a
significant percentage of the population were stricken by severe
attacks of myalgia we would anticipate the beginnings of a real
movement to release slaves, which would grow as news spread that the
phenomenon was not limited to the local slave owners, but was
endemic. No doubt, some would try to find loopholes, signing legal
documents, but changing nothing in real life – continuing to use
the slaves as if no papers had been signed. Your smart device being
too smart for this, however, the word would soon spread that evasion
did not work, and that the slaves would really need to be freed if
the owner was to avoid those episodes of complete agony. People are
remarkably flexible in their behaviors when it comes to avoiding
agony.
The
question is, would it be morally permissible for you to end slavery
in this way? Your action would be unlawful in every respect. You
would be violating criminal law on a massive scale. Necessity or
“lesser evil” defenses as traditionally understood are far too
narrow to provide you a defense of justification. In addition, you
have no sort of authority derived from any source even claiming
legitimacy.
I
am not going to go any distance into the question whether you are
morally prohibited from intimidating and torturing slaveholders on
the theory that “the ends can never justify the means.” This is a
not very accurate way of putting the “deontological” position
that sees moral principles as trumping good consequences. Many
deontologists entertain, at least by footnote, the possibility of a
“catastrophe override,” which permits the use of an otherwise
prohibited means if it obviates a sufficiently great evil. If a toddler
is two seconds away from stumbling onto the doomsday trigger and you
are 100 meters distant with nothing but a howitzer, the catastrophe
override on deontology may permit you to blow the tyke away.
I
find it hard to come up with a theoretical justification for
deontology without a catastrophe override, and for that reason, and
because slavery was a catastrophe sufficient to trigger the override,
I am going to assume that, insofar as there is anything to the slogan
“the end doesn't justify the means” it does not preclude you from
using your time machine and associated paraphernalia to end slavery.
Away
from the main course of the argument, I want to make a substantial
caveat. I am not here justifying the real world use of torture; nor
can anything like the argument I am making do so. Yes, in the purity of philosophical thought experiments, torture is sometimes
permissible. In the real world, a means as extreme and as universally
condemned as torture has to overcome an effectively insurmountable burden
of empirical proof that it will work, that nothing less egregious
will, and that the fallout for the reputation of the torturer will
not in the long run outweigh whatever might be gained by the torture.
Back
within the thought experiment, you are cloaked with not even the
thinnest mantle of legitimacy, in using unlawful force against
private persons. You are doing so to end an institution supported by,
arguendo, legitimate states (remember we are assuming Davis right
about secession). Those states are supported by a clear majority of
their citizens, and even, at least for some of the confederate
states, a majority of their population. How can you presume in this
extraordinary way against legitimate, and not horribly, horribly undemocratic
states?
A
legitimate state has a right to be wrong within a fairly broad range
of policy decisions. The more the state, through genuine democratic
mechanisms, reflects the choices of all of those subject to the
decisions, the wider the scope of its right to be wrong. At least
short of the ideal case of unanimity of a fully informed population,
however, there is always a limit on the right of even the majority
expressed through a legitimate state to be wrong. A little wrongness licenses protest, greater wrongness licenses unlawful resistance, and with wrongness beyond
that comes a right of revolution. Slavery was supported in the
Confederacy by a very imperfect form of democracy, but even had the
democracy been a good deal more robust, that would not have made
revolution morally impermissible.
So,
if you, as private individual without portfolio, could morally have
used torture and the threat of torture to end slavery, the conclusion
is not hard to reach that Lincoln could use force as well. His case was
better than yours in that he had, at least, pre-existing morally
significant ties to those residing in the seceding states who wished
to retain their relation to the United States. They were part of the
“people” for whom he was obligated to seek “the Blessings of
Liberty.” The methods he used, unlike those you used with your time
machine, were generally recognized by the community of nations.
There
are two objections that apply to Lincoln, but not to you. First, you
acted to end slavery. Lincoln acted primarily to keep intact the
union. Yet, the secession, first of South Carolina and then of the
other states, really was intimately tied to slavery.
It was Lincoln's uncompromising attitude against the extension of
slavery in the west that triggered the secession movement before he
was even inaugurated. Lincoln's use of force was from the beginning
enough about slavery to justify it even more clearly than you were
justified in using your time machine.
The
second objection is that you did not take an oath to uphold the
Constitution; Lincoln did. On the assumption I have been entertaining
throughout that Jefferson Davis was right about the constitutional
right of secession, didn't Lincoln violate his oath by forcibly
terminating the secession of the southern states? Is it moral to
violate so important an oath?
I
think Lincoln had available here an argument from conflicting
constitutional obligations. Even had the states a right of secession,
he did not violate his oath by forcibly putting these particular
secessions to an end. That argument, however, would would threaten to
become both too subtle and too convoluted. I omit it.
Better,
I think, to take the bull by the horns and say that Lincoln would
have been morally justified in violating his oath of office in
conducting a military campaign that, if successful, would inevitably
limit slavery substantially, and that, in fact, led to slavery's
abolition. Promises are important. Promises reinforced by the high
symbolism of inaugural oaths and the standing of a legitimate state
are of very great moral weight. But even the weightiest of promises
can be morally overcome. When slavery is on the other side of the
scale, it is not so easy to find anything that outweighs it.
No comments:
Post a Comment