There is no real controversy that the Republican tax act will
redistribute wealth upwards. Its best friends have persuaded themselves that it
will, however, benefit not only the Republican donor class, but the whole
country. Most taxpayers will get some tax cut, at least in the first years. Yes,
many will become medically uninsured. (That is, they will be “free to choose”
between no insurance and insurance they could not begin to afford.) And the cost
of health insurance will rise for everyone more than it otherwise would. Still,
these and other disadvantages for the poor and middle class will, it is
contended, be swamped by the tidal wave of new jobs and other benefits wrought
through the economic magic of the supply side. It will not be a trickle down, but a Niagara. People, especially
politician people, can persuade themselves of the darnedest things when those
things coincide nicely with their self-interest.
Let us throw all caution to the wind and make the assumption
that this is not wishful fantasy, but reality. The tax cut will benefit the
poorest among us. It might then seem that the act would pass muster under John
Rawls’s difference principle, which permits measures that increase inequality
so long as they benefit the least well off social class. Would the tax cut in fact be just if it benefited
everyone at least a little, but increased inequality substantially?
In fairness to Rawls, it must be said that the Trump tax act
wouldn’t really reach difference principle analysis because it would already be
disqualified by the lexically prior part of Rawls’s distributive justice scheme:
fair equality of opportunity. This principle requires that, in the race for
positions of influence and reward in the society, every child must get pretty
much an equal start. The chances that Barron Trump will grow up to be a CEO or
cabinet secretary and to own a befitting yacht, I conjecture, were already
rather better than the chances of the average
blue collar kid. The act tilted the playing field still more in his
favor by exempting yet more millions from the estate tax. The ability of the
wealthy to get themselves into powerful positions in business is obvious enough.
Their ability to assume high governmental positions or to place their agents,
friends, or relations into them is now effectively guaranteed by the Supreme
Court’s election-money-is-speech jurisprudence.
So the tax act flatly fails Rawls’s fair equality of
opportunity test. But let us put that aside and consider the difference
principle in isolation – on which the act initially looks better. At least, it would look better if we make one
more gigantic assumption. Let us suppose that the act not only benefits the
worst off class but that no alternative tax legislation that was less upwardly
redistributive would have benefited that class more. Probably we can find some
who believe even this, at least “within the limits of actual political
possibility.” My interest in making this assumption is not so much a matter of
real world political commentary, however, but of assuming into focus a
theoretical question: Should equality concerns sometimes take precedence even
over the absolute welfare of the worst off?
Forty years ago, I wrote an article on this topic, "Equality,
Solidarity, and Rawls' Maximin," (6 Philosophy and Public Affairs 262.)
Those were days when we were unaware that the chief influence holding back
egalitarianism would not come from the caution of liberals but from a hard
right turn in American politics. (It is interesting to speculate how far this
right turn was facilitated by the effective disappearance of the American left after
its brief flourishing in the 1960s. How important is it that the only critique
of the status quo that penetrated to the Wisconsin warehouse workers was
subsidized by Rupert Murdock, the Kochs, or the Mercers? Knowing that something
was out of joint, workers were told what it was by Rush Limbaugh or one of his
many well compensated clones.)
Much of the value of historical movements towards economic
equality has been in reducing outright misery by raising the standard of living
of the worst off groups and the strata just above them. I argued in 1977 and
still think today, however, that equality has a value in and of itself and it
would be a good thing if living standards were not different by too many orders
of magnitude bottom to top. This should, I think, sometimes take precedence
even over the welfare of the worst off.
Rawls must himself have believed in the independent force of
equality, otherwise he would not have so strongly advocated political equality,
equal basic liberties, and fair equality of opportunity. Justice does not, for Rawls, maximize liberty
for the group with least liberty. In A
Theory of Justice the liberty principle required “the most extensive basic liberty
compatible with similar liberty for others.” In Political Liberalism it became, “each person has an equal claim to a fully adequate scheme
of equal basic rights and liberties.” Why an equal right to run for
office, to vote, to speak, to associate, to snowshoe? The question almost
answers itself: because we are equally human, or, for some political rights,
equally citizens. That shared humanity or shared citizenship, without more,
requires these equalities of rights and liberties shows the independent moral
force of equality.
The difference
principle itself displays the independent value of equality. Equality is the default. It is departures
from equality that have to be justified by benefiting the worst off class. Now
here is the key question of this post: If equality has enough weight in
distributive justice to be the default, how can it be that an inegalitarian
program, however much it increases inequality, can be justified by any benefit
to the worst off class, however small be that benefit? It seems that could only
be so if equality itself were of no value at all. In that case why should it be the default,
and why its central position in the other principles of justice?
Despite a couple of
semesters in his classroom and several more teaching about his conception of
justice, I am not very good at channeling John Rawls. I think, however, that he might
respond here that I misunderstand his project. He was not laboring in the
laboratory of theoretical ethics, in which the sorts of arguments I tendered
might have some point. He was concerned with the justice of real societies in
the liberal tradition with histories, institutions, and public discourse. His
principles of justice were designed to be acceptable to rational participants
in that discourse. Perhaps in some philosopher’s thought experiment, intuition
might call for a small sacrifice in material welfare for the worst off in
exchange for a substantial decrease in the wealth gap. Political theory,
however, ought be conducted in and for the real world of political institutions
and people with political histories. For
that enterprise, the difference principle, unmodified is the right principle.
The
meta-philosophical issues raised by the Rawlsian distinction between moral
theory and political theory are of the first order of importance – but
difficult. Even if the distinction can
be clearly drawn and defended, I am not convinced that Rawls was right about the scope of
the data within the proper ken of the political theorist.
To explain, let’s go
back to the 1970s. It was then widely contended that any criticism of the
difference principle from the left could only come from some base and unworthy
source. “I’ll give back my 20 cents an hour wage bump if the boss will give up
his $2 million bonus.” That, it was said, is the voice only of spite and envy,
not of reason. Reason looks exclusively to self-interest and delights in Pareto
optimality.
This refrain, from the songbook of classical liberalism, misses some important facts about human societies and the social psychology of the beings that live in them. I have in mind some facts that communitarian political philosophies take more seriously than does classical liberalism. In 1977 I talked about “solidarity dispositions,” a terminology only partially apt. By whatever name, however, our sense of shared membership in society is important. When society is too severely divided those at the bottom will inevitably feel that they are not full members. Even those at the top sometimes concede that it is better to be surrounded by teammates than by flunkies. (Some, of course, really do love flunkies, but even their friends tend to doubt their mental health.)
This refrain, from the songbook of classical liberalism, misses some important facts about human societies and the social psychology of the beings that live in them. I have in mind some facts that communitarian political philosophies take more seriously than does classical liberalism. In 1977 I talked about “solidarity dispositions,” a terminology only partially apt. By whatever name, however, our sense of shared membership in society is important. When society is too severely divided those at the bottom will inevitably feel that they are not full members. Even those at the top sometimes concede that it is better to be surrounded by teammates than by flunkies. (Some, of course, really do love flunkies, but even their friends tend to doubt their mental health.)
Back to the
laboratory: There is a sole individual on a distant planet about whom we know
only through the newly discovered miracle of hyperspace signal bounding, and we know only a little. Other
things being equal, I should always be hoping that A’s life would keep improving. Yes, if A were already living very well, I might be a little envious, but
that would not be enough reason for me not to want to maximize A’s well-being. If
I found out that A were a member of a
society, I would still be fairly sure that small boosts in A’s well being were to be hoped for. A great leap that would leave A living much better than anyone else in
the society, however, would give me more to think about. Whether it was the
right thing would depend upon facts about the society, the ways its members
relate, and their social psychology.
In our society, for
better or worse, wealth is important. Beyond a certain point disparities in
wealth undermine community by creating sub-communities of great salience for
the nature of member interactions, for respect, and for self-respect. (Disparities in wealth also, inevitably, lead
to disparities in political power, but I leave this very important point aside
here because, for Rawls, the possibility of any serious disparities in
political power has already been dealt with by the prior principles of
justice.)
It is for these
reasons that, even if the Trump tax scheme lacked its estate tax component or
any other feature conflicting with fair equality of opportunity or equal basic
liberties and rights, and even if it had some benefit for the worst off, it
should yet be ruled unacceptable as a matter of political theory. It should be
rejected because it would dramatically increase inequality for a country in
which inequality is already far too dramatic.
Rawls, to give him
the final word, might well agree with the conclusion that the tax act is
unjust, but contend that this does not show the difference principle to be
wrong. The combined effects of other violations of the principles of justice
are at fault for the existing broad inequality. Were equal rights and fair
equality of opportunity observed, then there would already be significant
limitations on how far the economically blessed would dwell above the rest of
us. With those limits in place the difference principle would work just fine.
It would be impossible for a small benefit to the worst off to come at the cost
of a great increase in inequality because that great increase in inequality
would itself be impossible.
I am a little
skeptical, but do not rule this out. If
we were to take fair equality of opportunity seriously and with a sharp eye to
all the real world advantages of the wealthy, perhaps it would put a strict and
not very high ceiling on inherited wealth. With that ceiling in place, the difference principle looks very
different. It also makes Rawls more radical than he has usually been thought.
No comments:
Post a Comment