The
proposition that the universe is hospitable to human life,
potentially supporting a teleological argument for God, is
implausible at a first glance. So far as we now know with certainty,
the universe is congenial to human life only on the rind of one minor
planet of one among 1021
stars. Almost all of the real estate of the universe is distinctly
hostile to biological organisms, and this will remain the case as a
matter of the percentages even if the recent success in finding
extrasolar planets turns up some that are good candidates for life.
A
second glance, however, reveals some developments in theoretical
cosmology that may seem to give currency to the old saw that God made
the world for our use and enjoyment. Theists (and a few of the very
few deists there are) draw our attention to the “fine tuning” of
certain physical constants and initial conditions, a fine-tuning that
makes the existence of life possible.
The
“fine-tuning” label is, of course, already loaded. In our
experience only people tune things at all, roughly or finely. A more
neutral way of putting it is that the values of some physical
constants and some initial conditions of the universe must fall very
close to their actual values or we could never have developed –
because, among other inconveniences, atoms would have been wildly
unstable or the big bang would quickly have collapsed into a big
crunch or the matter of the universe would have run away from itself
too fast for stars to form. The constants in question include, among
others, the strong force, weak force, gravitational constant,
Planck’s constant, charge on the electron, speed of light,
cosmological constant, density of matter, and the number of “large”
dimensions. If any of these had been very different, we, apparently,
would not be.
There
are currently three major camps and one minor camp with respect to
the fine tuning of physical constants. Camp 1: The fine tuning is
exquisitely improbable, an improbability that can only be explained
by God. Camp 2: The fine tuning is exquisitely improbable, an
improbability that is, however, nicely explained if ours is only one
of many actually existing universes. Camp 3: The fine tuning may be
exquisitely improbable, but, if so, it is the sort of improbability
that requires no explanation. Because we are here it is inevitable
that the constants and conditions would be right for us. Camp 4:
Probabilities cannot properly be applied to the values of the
fundamental constants and initial conditions.
The
Camp 1, made up of deists and theists, has a straightforward
position. Physical theory shows that the basic constants and certain
big bang initial conditions must fall within a very small,
“Goldilocks zone,” for life to be a possibility in the universe.
That this should be the case is wildly improbable unless an
intelligence that is looking out for life was responsible for the
initial cosmic recipe.
Camp
2 goes along with Camp 1’s intermediate conclusion that, if this is
the only universe, then it would be wildly improbable that the
constants and initial conditions would fall within the Goldilocks
zone. The attractiveness of positing a creator who was looking out
for our interests disappears, however, if our universe is only one of
very many. Our sister universes will have all of the “bad”
values for the physical constants. It will be their misfortune that
atoms never form or that infant star systems collapse in an early
crunch. Making a modest borrowing from Camp 3, the members of Camp 2
argue that it is inevitable that we will be in one of the good (for
our existence) universes.
Camp
2 has astrophysics going for it – at least as of now. (These things
can change quickly.) There are good astrophysical reasons, quite
apart from the fine tuning question, to think that reality may well
be a multiverse. The currently most widely accepted “inflationary”
model of the Big Bang, is multiverse-friendly.
Camp
3, with Dawkins as honorary Camp Director, insists that no positive
probability, however low, for the constants and initial conditions
essential to human life is the least bit surprising or in any need of
explanation. No explanation at all is required for extraordinarily
improbable values of the physical constants. That a particular sperm
cell should fertilize a particular egg, leading to you, was an
astronomically unlikely event. You might reasonably feel grateful,
but you do not ask yourself, “How could this possibly have happened
without some extraordinary intervention?” Some great
improbabilities cry out for explanation; others are just the way
things fell out. It is a wonderful philosophical question just how we
are to draw the line between the two.
Dawkins
claims a partial solution to the what-needs-an explanation problem in
the famous “anthropic principle.” It is this principle
that serves as the founding charter of Camp 3. Observational results
that could not have been different if the observation was going to be
made at all never require special explanation. The principle in its
general form is related to observational bias in sampling. If I want
to know what percentage of animals are air breathers, I had better
not conduct the entire survey above the surface of the water. If
astrophysicists look out to see whether the universe has physical
conditions conducive to the development of astrophysicists, the
answer is inevitably going to be “yes.”
It
really is uncontroversially inevitable that, when astrophysicists
look out at the universe, they are bound to find it in a shape
consistent with their looking out at the universe. For that matter
they are bound to find it in a shape consistent with Custer’s
defeat at the Battle of Little Bighorn. Everything, including all of
the underlying physical properties of the universe must, of course,
be consistent with everything that is. To return to the problem from
a different direction, how far should this after-the-fact
inevitability count as a satisfactory explanation?
When
it comes to the conditions necessary for human life, Dawkins thinks
that the anthropic principle gives us all the explanation we should
seek.
the
beauty of the anthropic principle is that it tells us, against all
intuition, that a chemical model need only predict that life will
arise on one
planet in a billion billion to give us a good and entirely satisfying
explanation for the presence of life here (God
Delusion
138).
This
cannot be right in the way Dawkins puts it for the following reason.
If there is a second chemical model that predicts that life will
arise on one planet in a mere billion, that might well be a much
better explanation for life here, in which case the first model could
hardly be “good and entirely satisfying.” In fact, we would want
to know more about both models before deciding just how satisfied we
should be with either.
What
Dawkins might better have said is that it does not doom a chemical
model if it predicts life on one in a billion billion. An extreme
improbability could be part of our story without the necessity of any
further explanation of its extremity. But the move from “might not
require” to “does not require” explanation makes for an
aggressive use of the anthropic principle. This aggressiveness is
required to reach the conclusion that no explanation should be sought
even if the joint probabilities of everything’s falling within the
Goldilocks zone are infinitesimally small.
Let
me add one observation that does not justify Camp 3’s aggressive
anthropic principle, but should give that camp some comfort. The need
for an explanation of something does not follow from the possibility
of its having an explanation. Consider a nondescript pile of sand.
It would have an enormously complex grain by grain description and
and intimidatingly low antecedent probability of coming into
existence. It is possible that some super-engineer started from the
complete description and painstakingly assembled a pile of sand to
correspond. This would provide an explanation for why the pile of
sand is as it is. The possibility of such an explanation, however,
does not increase our desire or need for that or any similar sort of
explanation. God could well be the explanation for why the constants
are what they are, but that possibility does not itself mean that
there is a need for any explanation.
This
consideration does not, by itself, make a positive case for putting
the Goldilocks constants on the “no explanation needed” side of
the line. There are some worthy objections to doing so, but also
some serviceable responses to those objections. Pursuing this any
deeper would bring us into serious technical issues. So I am going
to leave the matter here for now without declaring either victory or
defeat for Camp 3. I am the more reconciled to this retreat because
there is a great deal to be said for Camp 4, which could put
Goldilocks to rest without any help from Camp 3’s strong anthropic
principle.
Before
heading on to Camp 4, it is worth acknowledging that a merger could
be negotiated between Camps 2 and 3. MIT astrophysicist and professor
of creative writing Alan Lightman: “We are an accident. From the
cosmic lottery that containing zillions of universes, we happened to
draw a universe that allowed life. But then again, if we had not
drawn such a ticket, we would not be here to ponder the odds.” (The
Accidental Universe: The World You Thought You Knew,
2013.) Of course, the more radical members of Camp 3 would consider
Lightman to be leading something of a hostile takeover. Dawkins, for
example, would insist that, with the anthropic principle in motion,
the multiverse is a fifth wheel on the Goldilocks bus.
It
is the Camp 4 position that is minor in the sense that it is least
talked about. It is also, so far as I can tell, correct. The idea is
that, although it might intuitively seem improbable that, e.g., the
charge on an electron should fall within one percent of its actual
value, there is no good way to give substance to that intuition.
We have a basis in past experience and physical analysis to apply a probability to a deuce on the next role of a given die. We have a basis for estimating the probabilities that a particular trial witness is lying. Nothing in our experience and nothing in our science, however, gives us a basis for assigning probabilities to the charge of an electron’s being within a certain range.
(Because all electrons have measured at a single value, to within experimental error, we have that basis for assigning a probability of one to the charge’s falling within one percent of its actual value. Camp 4 probability skepticism does not apply to that probability, but, of course, that probability is exactly the opposite of what the fine tuning argument needs, which is a very low probability not a very high one.)
There are, in addition, mathematical reasons for skepticism about the application of probabilities to the values of the fundamental constants (Timothy and Lydia McGrew and Eric Vestrup, “Probabilities and the Fine-Tuning Argument: a Sceptical View,” Mind 110 (2001): 1027-1037.)
We have a basis in past experience and physical analysis to apply a probability to a deuce on the next role of a given die. We have a basis for estimating the probabilities that a particular trial witness is lying. Nothing in our experience and nothing in our science, however, gives us a basis for assigning probabilities to the charge of an electron’s being within a certain range.
(Because all electrons have measured at a single value, to within experimental error, we have that basis for assigning a probability of one to the charge’s falling within one percent of its actual value. Camp 4 probability skepticism does not apply to that probability, but, of course, that probability is exactly the opposite of what the fine tuning argument needs, which is a very low probability not a very high one.)
There are, in addition, mathematical reasons for skepticism about the application of probabilities to the values of the fundamental constants (Timothy and Lydia McGrew and Eric Vestrup, “Probabilities and the Fine-Tuning Argument: a Sceptical View,” Mind 110 (2001): 1027-1037.)
Thus
Camp 4 argues that no probabilities, not even rough ones, can be
applied to the physical constants’ having values close to their
actual ones. With that, the fine tuning argument fails, at least in
its usual form. There is no infinitesimal probability to be
explained, and we do not even reach the Camp 3 issue whether it is
the sort of improbability that cries out for explanation. So, if
Camp 4 is right, then we do not need to postulate either a Fine Tuner
or a multiverse, although we might have other grounds for believing
in the existence of either or both.
To
sum up, the fine tuning argument faces three hurdles. Camp 4 has
underappreciated, but weighty, arguments that there is no
improbability in the apparent friendliness of the universe. Camp 3
gives good, if arguable, reasons to think no explanation would be
needed even if there were an improbability. Camp 2 gives an
attractive alternative explanation, supported by current
astrophysical theory, for the improbability if there is one and if it
needs to be explained.
For
these reasons, I do not now see here an argument for the existence of
God. However, there is just too much difficulty and too much
intellectual ferment to conclude that the Goldilocks array of
physical constants and initial conditions are unworthy of
consideration on the God question. For my own part, I take some small
comfort in the hope for the existence of a God who set things just
so. Wherever there is need for caution about the arguments that
derail an argument for God, it is some sort of plus for a theistic
hope.
This
post was excerpted from my book. Hope to
God. https://scribl.com/books/E9HZ8/hope-to-god. Also available as an Amazon e-book.
For more on hoping for the existence of a God for whom there
may be too little evidence for belief see my post of 5/5/15.
No comments:
Post a Comment