Bench trials (trial to a judge with no
jury) constitute about half of all criminal trials in the federal
courts and in the neighborhood of 15% of the felony trials. Yet they
are in flat contradiction to the express language of the
Constitution.
The constitutional text could not be
more explicit:
“The Trial of all Crimes, except in
Cases of Impeachment, shall be by Jury.” Art. III, §
2, clause 3.
This
occurs in Article III, which defines“the judicial Power of the
United States.” As an instrument establishing a limited
government, the Constitution flatly foreclosed the possibility of
federal criminal trials by combat or by ordeal, as argued in my post
of 12/15/14. It also forecloses trial by a judge sitting without a
jury.
This
may be an unwise constitutional provision. It might be very expensive
to hire the number of federal judges and prosecutors and to build the
new courtrooms that would be needed to afford jury trials to all
those accused of federal crimes. There is a strong tendency that
stretches from constitutional law scholars to barely literate
internet trolls and from the left to the right of the political
spectrum to honor the Constitution by reading it to conform, as much
as one can manage, to one's own political preferences. It is worth
reminding ourselves that not everything in the document ratified in
1787-1790 passes even the lowest standards for fundamental justice.
The fugitive slave clause is only the most obvious example. Equal
representation in the Senate, that egregiously anti-democratic
structural provision, was even placed by the founding fathers beyond
the possibility of any but unanimous state amendment. (Perhaps those
fathers did not take the non-amendment provision too seriously,
having themselves just ignored a very similar provision in the
constitutional regime under which they labored. See my post of
10/4/14, “Was the US Constitution Unconstitutional?”)
For
my own part, I am wary of consigning the jury provision
unconditionally to the dust bin of bad eighteenth century ideas for
the following reason. The crowding of federal judicial calendars is
in large part a function of our having so many federal criminal
statutes. Should we not be willing to pay for a proper criminal
process for those accused of any and all those acts we choose as a
nation to criminalize?
I
will admit that, although I have a generally high opinion of criminal
juries, I do not think that bench trials are currently a great blot
upon the justice of our criminal justice system. Plea bargaining,
however, my ultimate target, is a blot of enormous dimensions. It is
with that on the horizon that I would argue that we should only
criminalize what we can afford to reach judgment upon justly.
- Patton v. United States
Wise
or unwise, the Supreme Court has read the Article III jury
requirement out of the Constitution. “There is nothing in the
Constitution to prevent an accused from choosing to have his fate
tried before a judge without a jury” Adams
v United States ex rel McCann, 317
U.S. 269, 275 (1942). Adams
here relied ultimately on the interpretive precedent of Patton
v. United States 281 U.S. 276, 298 (1930). (To be fair to the
members of the Adams Court, Justices Douglas, Black, and
especially Murphy there expressed serious doubts about Patton
in dissent.)
Patton was authored by Justice
Sutherland, remembered by history as one of the “four horseman of
reaction” for his penchant for finding New Deal programs
unconstitutional by reading “due process” to constitutionalize a
laissez faire theory of freedom of contract. (Patton is
often said to have been “unanimous,” but the new Chief Justice
Hughes did not participate, Justice Sanford died before the date of
decision, and Justices Holmes, Brandeis, and Stone concurred only in
the result of this case involving 11 jurors by consent after one
juror became ill late in the trial. So the reasoning always cited as
the ultimate authority for the proposition that bench trials are
constitutional became a matter of record through the votes of only
four justices, and is arguably easily distinguished.)
The reason that Patton's holding
is understood to be decisive for the bench trial issue is that
Sutherland accepted the defense contention that eleven persons could
not constitute an Article III jury. “A constitutional jury means
twelve men . . .” at 292.
It is of some importance for the
precedential force of Patton whether we are to read “men”
here as “ungendered.” Sutherland was not as bad on women's
rights as you might expect, having supported the Nineteenth
Amendment. Yet his interpretive methodology would make the
gender-neutral move difficult for him. He drew heavily upon common
law history in establishing the “substantial and essential” jury
dozen. That same history would be at least as strong for the
exclusion of jurywomen. Maleness, so far as history would show, was,
like twelveness, one of the “common law elements . . . embedded in
the constitutional provisions.” Had Sutherland both the
imagination and the ideological flexibility to muse about this, he
might have concluded that the interpretation of “jury” ought not
be so tightly constrained by common law precedents. After all, “jury
of eleven” like “jury of men and women” were phrases that would
have been perfectly intelligible to, even if unprecedented for, late
eighteenth century speakers of American English. Subjects or citizens
who were not property owners had also been excluded from jury
service by the common law tradition. If women and the unpropertied
can constitutionally be jurors without defendant waiver, then the
common law tradition does not so tightly constrain the Article III
“jury” as Sutherland contended, and the defendant could have lost
this 11 juror appeal without a decision licensing the federal courts
to conduct bench trials.
- Sutherland's Chief Historical Arguments
In an earlier draft I itemized and
criticized eight arguments used by Sutherland to support his
contention that the jury requirement of Article III is waivable. I
then found a law review article that does a fine job of detailing
just how far out of the mainstream of prior Article III
interpretation Patton was and how shoddy were its historical
arguments. See Stephen A. Siegel, “The Constitution on Trial:
Article III's Juror Trial Provision, Originalism, and the Problem of
Motivated Reasoning,” 52 Santa Clar L Rev. 373 (2012). "Akhil Amar is restrained when he says "None of the arguments in Patton v. United States survives close scrutiny." Siegel at 417, Akhil Amar, "The Bill of Rights as a Constitution," 100 Yale L. J.1131 at 1197.
As Siegel exhibits, Sutherland
throughout places the burden of proof on the natural reading of the
provision. For Sutherland it counts heavily against this
“structural” or “jurisdictional” interpretation that the
eighteenth century drafters, pamphleteers, journalists, and debaters,
never explicitly said that the Article III jury requirement was
unwaivable. That none of these sources of quotations ever breathed
the possibility that the jury provision could be waived was,
apparently, unworthy of interpretive notice.
Sutherland brushes aside the fact that
defendants could not in general waive the jury requirement in
England. This, he asserts, was the result of specifically English
conditions, in particular that the father's felony conviction cut off
his heir from the estate. Sutherland fails to ask whether criminal
convictions in the United States might ever have an affect on third
parties and so support non-waivability of juries for the same
general reason as in England. Removing the father from the farm or
the master from the shop would affect the life prospects of wife and
children and often of apprentices, journeymen, suppliers and
customers. Conceivably Blackstone might not have considered these
plebeian concerns as having the same weight as the loss to his heir
of the lord's estate, but it is difficult to imagine Ben Franklin's
concurring in that assessment. In fact, the American colonists had
their own historically specific reasons for being pro-jury and for
being suspicious of judges, often tools of the crown.
At a higher level of generality,
Sutherland argued that there was, in the United States, no rational
basis at all for any jury requirement other than a waivable right. He
develops this through quotations from the dissent of Judge Aldrich in
Dickinson v. United States, 159 Fed. 801 (1st
Cir. 1908). Aldrich ridiculed “the idea that the constitutional
safeguards in question were in any sense established as something
necessary to protect the state or the community from the supposed
danger that accused parties would waive away the interest which the
government has in their liberties, and go to jail.” Dickenson
at 820, Patton at 295. “There is not now, and never was,
any practical danger of that. Such a theory, at least in its
application to modern American conditions, is based more upon useless
fiction than upon reason.” Dickenson at 820 , Patton
at 296.
Perhaps it is fiction to suppose that
anyone would ever waive trial rights preferring the relative safety
of incarceration to the tender mercies of his enemies on the streets
or out of inability to cope with the increasingly unfulfilled needs
of an impoverished family. It is fiction of the sort that Dickens
might write, which, to be sure, may well have seemed quite useless to
Aldrich, Sutherland, and their social circles. Sutherland reads the
text of document of the eighteenth century, a much more communitarian
time, through the lens of early twentieth century economic and
political individualism.
We now know that the great majority of
accused, in fact, waive their trial rights altogether, and that among
them are a disturbing number who are innocent of the crime pleaded
to. The national community has its own interest, quite independent of
the interest of the accused, in convicting only the guilty, indeed in
convicting only those who can be shown to be guilty beyond a
reasonable doubt in a process that both is, and appears to be, fair.
Convicting the innocent not only has the obvious human costs for the
immediate and the secondary victims, but is a security negative. It
undermines confidence in the criminal justice system and, arguably,
decreases crime control. “The funny thing is - on the outside, I
was an honest man, straight as an arrow. I had to come to prison to
be a crook." Andy Dufresne - The Shawshank Redemption.
Aldrich and Sutherland were just wrong.
There is a reason to protect the state and community with something
stronger than waivable rights. The plain meaning of the jury
requirement of Article III is not so crazy that courts must come up
with an alternative reading.
- The Judiciary Act Argument
Sutherland calls attention to sections
9 and 12 of the Judiciary Act of 1789, which make use of the same
“shall be by jury” language that is found in the Article III
provision with which we are concerned. He notes that “many who had
participated in the convention which framed the Constitution”
were members of this first Congress.(at 300-301) That much is right.
The Senate on any day it sat in 1789 would have had a majority or
near majority of signers of the Constitution. The House's
representation of Conventioneers stood at about 15%, although one was
a non-signer. Madison was in the House, however, which probably means
that effective framer presence was about equal in the two chambers.
Constitutional interpretation has often
drawn upon evidence from the First Congress. This is justified on a
framers' intent theory, on a ratifiers' intent theory, and, of
course, on a framers' and ratifiers' intent theory. The great
majority in both houses participated in the ratification process of
their respective states. Actions of the First Congress are also
relevant for a theory looking to the meaning of the text for fluent
speakers of the enactment period, although Congressional doings and
historical materials are not much more relevant than other
contemporaneous writings.
Sometimes the records of the early
Congress are pretty good evidence of how key Constitutional language
was then understood. The reference to religion as a desideratum for
education in the Northwest Territories Act, for example, surely has
some bearing on what “establishment” was understood to mean.
Had the First Congress passed an act
setting out the procedures for bench trials upon defendant waiver,
that would have been the basis for a serious interpretive argument.
Congress did nothing of the sort, however, for over a hundred years.
It is not anything the First Congress did that supports Sutherland's
waivable right theory, it is that the Supreme Court, several years
after the First Congress ended, started to interpret the Section 2
and Section 9 provisions in terms of waivable rights. Perhaps a
rather tortuous precedent argument can be put together out of these
materials, but not a serious argument relying on the fact that
members of the First Congress were framers, ratifiers, or fluent
speakers of their era.
4. Careful
Scrutiny and Intentional Misdrafting
I cannot resist going into a little
detail on one additional part of Sutherland's excursion into history.
The argument is so lame that I will quote it verbatim to avoid the
suspicion that I am mischaracterizing. It addresses the “imperative”
nature of the Article III language in light of his observation that
the contemporaneous literature did not discuss non-waivabilty. “This
is all the more remarkable when we recall the minute scrutiny to
which every provision of the proposed Constitution was subjected. The
reasonable inference is that the concern of the framers of the
Constitution was to make clear that the right of trial by jury should
remain inviolable, to which end no language was deemed too
imperative.”
In other words the restriction on the
federal courts that “the trial of all crimes . . . shall be by
jury” was not really intended to prohibit trial of crimes by means
other than jury, but was an intentional overwriting to reinforce the
inviolability of the defendant's right to a jury. This right, of
inviolability so strong that no language could be too imperative, was
nonetheless waivable. Sutherland apparently believed intentional
misdrafting for emphasis was not only consistent with, but
apparently a product of, that “minute scrutiny” to which the
provision, like all provisions, was subjected. One might have naively
thought that minute scrutiny must have revealed the possibility that
the provision might be read as written, that is as a prohibition of
federal non-jury trials. Couldn't some wording less susceptible to
misreading have been found to set out (even with emphasis) a waivable
right?
5. The
Argument From Guilty Pleas
Bench trials in criminal were
apparently unknown or very nearly unknown in 1789 with the exception
of minor offenses and the exception of the state of Maryland. See
Siegel at 419, n. 263. See generally, Susan C. Towne, “The
Historical Origins of Bench Trials for Serious Crime,” 26 Am. J.
Legal Hist. 123, (1982). Guilty pleas, however, had long existed,
although they may never have been very common. This historical fact
gave rise to a Sutherland argument that deserves some special
attention because it remains seductive to this day. If an accused can
waive trial altogether, isn't it a matter of logic that he can also
waive each of the particular protections and rights of a trial,
including the jury? Isn't it a metaphysical truth that the whole
includes the part? For a touch of the real world, recall that the
right to a jury is one of the specific rights that a defendant is now
required to renounce, personally, voluntarily, and knowingly, in open
court for a plea of guilty to be accepted by the judge.
Remaining at this level of pure theory,
the problem with this argument is that it proves too much. The right
to be tried by a jury has the lesser included right not to be tried
by combat. This is the point at which you might want to take a look
at my prior post. I would hazard that Sutherland would not have
contended that the fact that an accused can plead guilty, and hence
waive a jury trial, implies that anyone could waive his or her way
into a trial by combat. If Sutherland would concede this point,
however, his argument from guilty pleas falls away.
This is an issue to which we will need
to return when we get to plea bargaining. As far as bench trials are
concerned, we could rest with the pre-Patton understanding
that accepting judgment without trial was one thing, but, if a trial
took place in a federal court, Article III required that it be a jury
trial.
6. Conclusion on Bench Trials and Interpretive Lessons to Be Drawn
Siegel does not fault Sutherland for his conclusion that the Article III jury requirement is waivable. Sutherland's interpretive mistake, Siegel thinks, was in using originalist interpretive methods in reaching this conclusion – methods that required him to make such a mess of the history. Sutherland should have adopted a method of constitutional construction that brought the current needs of the courts directly to bear on the Article III provision, following the progressive jurisprudence of Holmes and Pound. Siegel: “we must develop public law jurisprudences that embrace and grow from, rather than deny, the observation that the infusion of contemporary values into constitutional law is inevitable.” at 452.
I have no desire to defend Sutherland's framer's intent version of originalism. I do, however, think it is important that what was ratified, and so has the stamp of legitimacy, was a text. Like any text it was composed of specific words and phrases. Contemporary values will and should be infused into constitutional law when a judge applies “due process,” “cruel and unusual punishments” or “just compensation.” That is what the text requires.
Precedent aside, a judge must give her best judgment of what process is due. The Constitution does not list permissible processes and was not written in terms of “procedures accepted in 1789 as due process.”
When it comes, however, to interpretation of “neither shall any person be eligible to that office who shall not have attained to the age of thirty-five years,” there being no normative terms, there is no point at which contemporary values can be infused. “The Trial of all Crimes, except in Cases of Impeachment, shall be by Jury” similarly is not subject to contemporary values on the question whether some crimes can be tried other than by jury. If the provision is a bad one, it should be amended. An argument could be made that “jury” was a legal term of art with a normative dimension – that what would count as a jury was an evolving concept with ingredients of fairness and peer representation. There is, however, no good argument that “all” was quasi-normative.
So, I am happy to endorse Siegel's critique of Sutherland's historical analysis, and I also agree with Siegel in thinking that attempts to divine what was in the minds of the drafters or ratifiers either with respect to intent or expectation is liable to produce interpretations highly correlated with the interpreters own political predilections. I think Siegel goes astray, however, in thinking that a sound democratic political theory is compatible with a Constitution that can “grow” in conflict with its own enacted meaning. For this reason I think Siegel is as wrong as Sutherland in concluding that federal criminal bench trials are constitutional.
(For a more detailed, and more theoretical, discussion of the sort of textualist interpretive methodology I suggest here – a methodology that keeps normative terms normative, rather than converting them into descriptions, see my post of 6/17/14 “A Testualist Approach to Legal Interpretation.”)
No comments:
Post a Comment